TRENDS IN PHILOSOPHY OF TECHNOLOGY
Commented
book review of Daniel Cérézuelle's
La Technique et la Chair: Essais de
Philosophie de la Technique
Lyon:
Parangon/Vs, 2011
by Kristo Ivanov, Umeå University, (April 2012, version
160320-2035)
(A
short version of this paper was published by Amazon.ca,
Amazon.com
and Amazon.co.uk)
TABLE OF
CONTENTS
Introduction
- Publisher's summary (translated from the French)
Part 1: Approaches to the spirit of
technicism
Part 2: The onslaught of technology and its disruptive
effects
Part
3: The flesh, technology, time
The
book's appendix: Details about the notion of flesh
Facts,
and theoretical background
Religion
as producer of symbolism
Computerization
and theology of mathematics-logic
A
Case Study: engagement, involvement, embodiment
The Case Study
illustrated: a dissertation on embodiment
The publisher's and the author's joint
presentation of the French book reviewed here, with the translated title Technology and the Flesh: Essays on Philosophy
of Technology, states that one cannot understand the technological
dynamics of our civilization without taking into account a spirit of technicism
that has nothing to do with utilitarian reason. That is why the field of the
technological imaginary is of crucial political importance. The pace of
expansion of our technological system is increasingly unsustainable. Many signs
suggest it is already reaching its limits and that if we are to avoid
ecological and social chaos it will be necessary to make wrenching revisions; a
radical rethink of our consumerist and technicist lifestyle seems inevitable.
Such a policy will face a formidable obstacle: beliefs and the collective
imaginary. Mobilizing the notion of flesh as a thread, the essays in this
volume offer an exploration of this technological imaginary. The relation of
man to modern techniques is necessarily mediated by an imagination that is
organized in sensory myths as much as in abstract ideas. Similarly it is
because man is a being of flesh that the rapid deployment of technological
power can have disruptive effects, even dehumanizing ones, individually and
collectively. But to mention the idea of a renunciation to certain forms of
power, it is to suggest to the "man-of-the society-of-development" to
tear off his skin; he does not know how to respond except by a call for more
technology. Yet it is because that man is a being of flesh that it is vital to
impose a slower rate of technological change: a difficult task for which we are
poorly prepared and for which one of the first conditions is to proceed towards
demythologization of our technological imaginary.
To dwell in the issues considered in
this demanding book is, to use its own words (p. 9), to risk to commit a
political or professional suicide; unless it is done after retirement, that is.
I feel qualified to confirm this on the basis of my own experience from the
computer industry and the university world. And it is probable that the author
himself, Daniel
Cérézuelle, has had to pay a
considerable price for passionately having pursued such studies in the
philosophy of technology. The book is so far available only in French,
targeting mainly French-speaking countries like France and Canada. The author,
who we will refer to as "the author", presents himself as a student of philosophy and social
sciences, having taught in France and the United States. Currently he is
engaged in areas related to sustainable development and conducts research in
philosophy of technology and the socializing role of non-monetary economy.
In the spirit of the book I will use the term "technology" for the French "technique". One main message of the book
is that the ongoing expansion of technology and its applications is the result
of a technological spirit or frame of mind that is not utilitarian and
consciously goal-directed but rather culturally conditioned. Indeed, while I
was writing these lines I read about what undergraduate students of informatics
at a Swedish university are concluding in an assignment on "future
studies" in a course on the future digital media. Their vision is:
"Touchscreens in tables and on walls, cameras in the lens of the eye,
fingerprints instead of credit cards, the TV becomes a computer and digital
games are controlled by bodily movements in large rooms..." Not a single
word about essence of, or research on creativity, or about the difference
between is and ought, between will be and should be, about whether it is
foreseen to be good or bad and for whom, or for that matter who will pay and
who may at least profit of it. Imagination is childishly let free at somebody's
or taxpayers', or consumers' expenses, as in typical imaginative and playful
advertising for futuristic levitating cars and whatnot. Forget about old style
serious university research or investigative journalism: universities often
prefer to keep surfing on the possible applications of available commercial and
industrial products whose prior development is left to industrial laboratories.
Goals and culture? If there are any goals they are the market's, whatever that
is. Or, as a friend expresses it: the "objectives" end at the point
of sale. Or at the point of the researchers cashing their research grants. Or
at the point of the students receiving their passing grade.
According
to the book's the driving cause of this state of affairs is the culturally
conditioned technological imaginary (in Gilbert Durand's meaning) that is illustrated in the first of
the three parts of the book in terms of history of theology and philosophy.
They are seen to relate to the spirit of technology by means of analysis and
commentaries of literature and films. The second part builds up an image of
consequences of technology beyond questionable profits, while the third part is
directed toward a sort of conclusion in terms of unacceptability or
impossibility of long term consequences, and of what should be done.
In what follows, for stylistic reasons, I will refer to myself as
(representing) "the reader", and thereby I will differentiate between
the author's statements, and my own personal comments that will gradually
increase in number along the course of the chapters. The next five sectionf
below, including the "Appendix: Details about the notion of flesh"
are an account of the book itself. The following "Some final
comments" about the whole, with its subsections are mine. All translations
from the French original text are mine. For the rest I wish to alert the
readers that my intentional profusion of references and links in the text only
aims at supporting further investigations including my own as related to my
earlier work. For this I make extensive albeit not exclusive use of Wikipedia-references because of their
comprehensiveness, and easy overview in terms of standardized layout, with full
knowledge and evaluation of their possible shortcomings. All this explains the volume of
text of my review that is expanded from the idea of a simple book review to a
survey of its context as platform for research.
Part 1: Approaches to the spirit of technicism
The first part of the book in its chapter I is dedicated
to illustrate how human thought, or "reason", or "spirit",
from its known beginning long before the rise of science in the 16th and 17th
centuries has been trying to "divinize" man. He has been being
unconsciously seduced by a "desire for power" to transcend the limits
of presumed human condition in the "reality", in terms of
materiality, time, and space. This enterprise is illustrated by history: magic,
myths embodied in literature or media, philosophy, and ultimately by repeated
reforms and final abandonment of theological interpretations. The dream was
early expressed also in the attempt to liberate the energy or spirit hidden
inside nature and matter in order to trespass the ontological limits of human
existence and to offset its perceived incompleteness. That is, it is a desire
for power that has nothing to do with usefulness, and explains why the
"vocation of the tool" is to transform itself sooner or later in
weapon, and contribute to the "progressive production of God via
evolution" (p.28). The technological striving for power and its
characterization of deepest layers of modern Western thought is the recurrent
theme of the book. The reader may note that this criticism recalls the classic
notion of hubris, considered the greatest crime of ancient Greek
society, something
that is not recalled in its text.
Chapter II illustrates how the attempts were initially
made by means of magic and the presumed understanding of divine intentions
through knowledge of the system of forces or powers in nature. Cabbalism and Lullism are examples of conceptions that systematized the play of
divine cause in combinatorial and numerical terms, opening the way towards a
later mathematization of the understanding of nature. By means of mathematics
one would be able to acquire further knowledge of the divine secrets of nature
without the need of a particular virtue, mainly by means of
"mechanical" (mathematical) operations. In this sense our modern
solutions are analog to those of magic, gnosis, and hermeticism (p. 47). Even if the reference is
not mentioned in the book the reader may note that this aspect of technology
has been well noted by scholars like Frances Yates, and Richard Stivers in his book Technology
as Magic, where Stivers is heavily influenced by Jacques Ellul, known as French
philosopher, law professor, sociologist, lay theologian, and Christian anarchist. Stivers' book explains symbolism in
language still better than our reviewed book and recalls questions that are
common to the Toronto School of media theorists including Marshall McLuhan,
Walter Ong, Neil Postman and related Douglas Rushkoff. It deals with
"magic" in the crisis of language vs the rise of visualization and
aestheticism, the dominion of statistical information through computers, mass
media and public opinion, therapies and self-help ideologies, management fads,
and education in universities in decline. Furthermore, we have the related Religion
of Technology by David Noble and more
contemporary studies relating these issues to trends in computer science, such
as a PhD dissertation by
Erik Persson (2002), partly summarized in an article in
the Ellul Forum (Spring
2009) betitled (and available in pdf-format) as "Cybergnosticism Triumphant?" Most users including researchers of interaction
between man and machine in the IT/ICT-field (information and communication
technologyl) handle the products just by pressing
keys in keyboards, without any idea about what happens "inside" or
why it works. They may be seen as perceiving and acting as in a magic world: it
"works" but one does not know why. Magic will work the more so when
people in they "everyday life" have no views about what is good or
bad, and for whom, but are content with their salary while fostering the
"aesthetic" or aestheticist design of edutainement, interaction, engagement,
involvement, presence or whatever.
The first part of the book includes
also (chapter III) a review of the role of the relation between technique as
crafts, and science for power or mastery over nature. This recalls in the mind
of the reader the relation between the much advertised and little
reflected-upon concept of tool,
vs. machine
or instrument
where the book makes important distinctions between a tool that stays under the
control of the human agent, and machine, inaugurated with the steam engine.
This is done by dwelling on the implications that the Euclidean apodictic
method had for mathematization or formalization of the sciences, and for the
consequent partial divorce between science and experience, contrasted to
experimentation. In this context appears the famous quotation from Descartes
that in true science "We must deal only with objects about which our minds
seem to suffice to acquire a certain and
indubitable knowledge" [Il faut s'occuper seulement des objets dont nos esprits semblent
suffire à acquérir un connaissance certaine et indubitable].
It prompts the author to recall that the "revolution in reason" was
not a revolution of reason (p.60).
That is: "This
was a decision to limit the ontological horizon of reason. Objects of thought
that are too difficult are excluded. The revolution in reason cannot be explained
logically, it is posited as a new requirement that the human will must assume
and carry out." The reader may ask: "carry out successfully?",
whatever that means or should mean.
A chapter (IV) is dedicated to
"technological violence" and deals with risk and danger as conceived
in film and literature. Examples are given of how catastrophes are depicted as
unavoidable or caused by incompetence, ill-willed villains or terrorists, all
under the assumption that goodwill shall prevail under the aegis of democratic
technology. Risks justify the taking of risks through the idea of insurance,
furthering the "insurance industry". The reader is led to wonder
whether this conception may also explain the ongoing emphasis on preventing and
combating terrorism that seems to feed upon certain forms of technological
power. The author's analysis goes on identifying features of the narratives
such as fantasies on transgressions of moral and physical limits of reality,
including infantile yearnings of omnipotence
and transgender behavior or asexuality. This is a hidden ideology of "no
consequences" (cf. "polymorphous
perversity") or
irresponsible behavior where no consequences of actions have to be reckoned
with. It becomes obvious for the reader that such a scenario recalls a possible
staging of aestheticism
as in today's emphasis on "design", ludic behavior
as in computer
games, as well as present GLTQ-trends
in Western societies that are associated with branches of feminism.
The natural reality of biological diversity is downplayed or outright denied in
favor of a technologically supported idea of gender's social
construction in a world where,
for instance, biological functions are artificialized.
Chapter V on "virtual
existences" considers the ongoing technologically supported process of desincarnation
(and therefore dehumanization, in the book's frame of mind of emphasis on
"flesh"), and violence, with its implicit deconstruction of sexual
gender identities and denial of biological-social constraints, as well as of
consequences of human actions and risks in physical-biological reality. It is
illustrated through commentaries on better known films and pieces of
literature. Examples are Screamers by
Christian
Duguay; Crash,
The Fly and EXistensZ by David
Cronenberg; The Matrix, by Andy and Larry
Wachowski, Avalon,
by Mamoru Oshii.
The reader may notice some parallel insights are contained in other studies
such as the earlier mentioned PhD dissertation by Erik Persson, summarized in
the article (pdf-format) on Cybergnosticism
Triumphant? The book's
theoretical framework purports to offer a description of the "soul's
anatomy" and of the socio-ethical disorientation of the addict to computer
games such as World
of Warcraft whatever else is
suggested by a novel like Ursula Poznanski's Erebos
and its ethically neutral reviewers, e.g. for Swedish readers in the newspaper Dagens
Nyheter. No lack of
"engagement-involvement" here (see more below, at the end of this
review). The reader may also notice that the mentioned plots have a deal in
common with the core of the Swedish success cast figure Lisbeth Salander,
as well as complications in contemporary sexual relations, emphasis on radical
feminism, gender-wars, homosexuality, bisexuality, transgender, cisgender,
and euphemisms for promiscuity. They may be summarized by the abuses of feminism,
of the so called LGBT
and polyamory
movements, and illustrated by some of the ultimate behaviors described
scientifically as early as in 1886 by Richard
von Krafft-Ebing in his Psychopathia Sexualis, and as late
as in the afterwar's weird art like The
Ballad of Genesis and Lady Jaye,
or filmic
environments related to the Church
of Satan and
their influence on present computer-game settings. The reader, however, will usually not go to such
extremes in the reflections upon the chapter. It
may be enough to perceive subtle syntheses of the messages in both chapters IV
and V by interpreting the content of teen-age oriented best-sellers like the
Swedish Cirkeln,
in a trilogy by Mats Strandberg and Sara Bergmark Elfgren, 2012), that has been described as a
"Harry Potter pastiche", obviously exploiting the Harry Potter
successful pattern. It was unsuspectingly reviewed in the main newspaper Dagens
Nyheter
(18 April 2011) with the naive
comment that the more powerless a group of people (read: teenagers) feel (or
are pretended to be) in society, the greater the need for them to invoke
omnipotent and romanticized incarnations as vampires and magicians. And the
publisher's choice of an appreciative quotations from writer John
Ajvide Lindqvist claims that it
deals with group dynamics, identity, understanding one's place in the world,
and on how to become a human.
The first part ends with chapter VI on the "metaphysics of accident"
and its purpose is to give a sort of historical, phenomenological
and psychological insight into the development of human attitudes to
risks and accidents, with emphasis on the fascination of speed and the "disparity in nature between human and technical
time" (p. 112). It starts from reflections upon traditional philosophy's
differentiation between accident and essence, it goes further to early
perceptions of bureaucratic depersonalization,
and to early accidents with what we today see as an antiquated technological
system such as described in Thomas de Quincey's The English Mail Coach
(1849). The text is interspersed by challenging reflections. One of them is on
the "perverse inversion between the essential and the accidental"
whereby we come to see increased rates of accidents as both inevitable, normal
and perfectly acceptable. So arise "technical fatalities" that in
fact imply a willful renounce to know the context and consequences of our
actions. Earlier in the book (p. 67f.) this is exemplified by the estimate that
by the year 2020 traffic accidents will be the third most common cause of
deaths and invalidity in the world, after cardiovascular diseases but before
wars and AIDS. Another series of reflections deals with the downplaying of
dangers in the name of rejected or denied "improbable possibilities"
while paradoxically praising technology's proud capability to make possible
what seemed to be impossible. Several related expressions find their place in
the text, such as "the unlikely possibility can become real", or
"the real is no more necessary than the possible" (quoted from Sören
Kierkegaard's Philosophical fragments).
At this point the reader will readily
recall the Fukushima
nuclear disaster, as well as its relation
to the Chernobyl nuclear accident.
One thoughtful concluding reflection is that "the real is more complex
than we know" or imagine (p. 101). While re-reading this chapter (VI)
("Métaphysique de l'accident") as part of my obstinate struggle for
this review it occurred to me that I must include a reference to a genial
video-sketch Om
sannolikhet [On probability] by
the late Swedish author, actor, poet and film
director Tage
Danielsson. It is a video with English
subtitles, referring to the famous Three Mile Island
accident, south of Pennsylvania's capital Harrisburg in the
USA in 1979 (there is on the net also an alternative video source and the translated written text). The kind
of reflections raised in the book regarding the concept of probability would
have allowed the construction of a bridge over to a systems theory on the base
of critical analysis of probability such as the one advanced by West Churchman
in his Prediction
and Optimal Decision. That kind of systems theory
would have answered many of those questions that, as we shall see later in the
book, appear to be left unanswered by the phenomenological approach espoused by
the author.
The second part of the book starting with chapter
VII (p. 119) deals with consequences of the technical imaginary, mainly in
"case studies" in the fields of biotechnologies and informatics.
Especially biotechnologies put into evidence that technology in not simply
"transitive" in the sense of a tool obeying voluntary actions of a
human subject upon an inanimate object. Reflexivity comes into play when a
subject' or agent's technologically supported power of action affects subjects
or agents including himself, and their own subsequent will. This is most
visible in techniques affecting births and reproduction, transplantation, and
such, including then e.g. redefinitions of death. So called bioethics, in the
name of good-willed intentions risks to mask the risks. It assumes a free will,
free from social constraints, with full consciousness and freedom of choice in
a liberal pluralist society living up to an Anglo-Saxon democratic ideology. It
assumes this for well defined professionals, working with a statute in a
transparent institutional context. This disregards that technology eventually
becomes banalized and is practiced outside a narrows professional context, and
is submitted to sociological pressures that challenge the image of ideal
independent moral agents. Socialist reformers of the past at least acknowledged
the need for a "social reorganization" to meet this type of
challenges. Besides this, rational ethical imperatives such as in "codes
of conduct" presume a feeling of responsibility that, in turn, is grounded
in a individuality or "who am I?". Such an individuality is today
shaken by concrete organ transplantation, prosthesis, sex change or
transgender practices, but especially by the parallel questioning of individuation including
the related filiation and sperm donation.
Ultimately the question becomes "who is the subject of ethical life"
when it turns out that ethical voluntarism does not
work. Means are created in view of ends but on the other hand they impose their
own constraints. Even those who do not endorse the claim that technological
progress is autonomous will agree that it cannot be stopped, despite of the
absence of total overview and goals. The author concludes the need for a moratorium
and an ethics of "non-power" in the shadow of Jacques Ellul's
pessimistic quotation "the supreme luxury of this civilization of
necessity [of unavoidable progress] is to grant me the superfluity of a sterile
revolt, and a willing smile". Symptomatically the same feeling arised in
me upon meeting the Swedish judicial system in a matter related to the
"Society for Cutting Up Men", S.C.U.M.
and to the political correctness of militant radical feminism that is also
supported by "masculine" power technology.
Similar conclusions are draw from a
following chapter (VIII, p. 151ff.) on "ethics and informatics" where
the latter is structured as the storage, processing and transmission of
information. In historical contrast to other techniques, computer and
information science are noted for being inextricably both science and
technology, or theoretical technology, rather than applied science. For those
who like me are familiar with this field it is easy to verify (and extrapolate
into other chapters) the trustworthiness of the book's analysis of various
issues. Examples are the abuse of citizens' data bases that rely on
de-individualizing personal identification numbers (PIN), the impotence of a
professional codes of ethics,
the limitations of the efficacy of the formal requirement of the registered
people's informed
consent, the overconfidence in state regulatory
organs corresponding to the Swedish Data
Inspection Board compared with the
need of public morality, the misunderstanding of privacy in typically
individualist and liberal approaches that ignore the realities of public life
and the ongoing gradual merge between private and public life (cf.
individuation), the increased centralized control of citizens by the state in
general, and by the police in particular under the pretext of preventing accidents
and terrorism as related to powerful and sensitive technology, the automation
and degradation of personal skills and consequent unemployment in computerized
work environments, and so on. It is easy to agree with the author that such
developments characterized by piecemeal, incrementalist approaches require much
more than "deontological
recommendations" (p. 152ff.).
But it will not help that the author
complains about "our dependence upon the incomprehensible" of
excessively complex technology, and that he consequently calls for an
ethics-based on debate and politicization of technical choices, prudence,
slowness, or "respect for the Kantian principle of humanness that requires
abstention from total objectivation of the subjects social life". Ethical
voluntarism, as acknowledged in earlier parts of the book, will not do when
available technology conditions human will and does not encourage or even
permit choices. Finally the author acknowledges that the politicization of
ethics (that the reader may equate to overconfidence in democracy) does not
eliminate the risk of incontinence
or wantonness, i.e. willing evil despite of knowing the good. Nevertheless, the
chapter remarkably ends in an appeal to renunciation to certain technological
possibilities and to a call for an "ethics of non-power", a kind of
paradox that the reader notes, and will appear more and more often in the rest
of the book. It may recall in the reader's mind Carl Jung's
statement (in his On the Psychology of the Unconscious, Collected Works, CW 7, §78) that logically, the opposite of love is
hate, and of Eros, Phobos (fear); but psychologically it is the will to power.
One can then easily draw the conclusion, about what has been forgotten in the
calls for non-power, moratorium, and such, and why I do not look for, say, the
psychoanalyst of power Alfred Adler
despite power being a central issue in our book, as I do not look for Hannah
Arendt with her insightful writings on power
and violence. Ultimately it may
not be a question of power but, rather, love in its particular meaning of charity.
The following chapter IX (p. 159ff.)
deals with technology related to breakdown of civilization or culture at the
daily life's "street-level" that could be included in what today in
the English language is associated with
"local-informal-manual-ecological-sustainable". The reader may
realize that in the academic world some aspects of this have been acknowledged
under the label of civil society,
but more closely to the capability approach
related in knowledge-information terms to tacit knowledge
and to knowledge management,
raising particular problems in the computer-related field of knowledge engineering.
The whole point of the chapter, however, is to emphasize that modern technology
and especially what in France is called "techno-science" tends to
oppress and destroy street-level culture or the basic cultural texture of daily
life. For this purpose the author refers to, among others, to his own earlier
book (in French, 1996 For
a Different Social Development), and Amartya Sen's (only in French, L'économie est Une Science Morale
(Economics is a Moral Science, with comments
in English by Angus Sibley).
It in this chapter that the reader
will note that author starts referring in increasing scale to the concept of symbolism that progressively, in the
later text appears associated to (mainly) Ernst Cassirer,
and, further to Maurice
Merleau-Ponty, and André
Leroi-Gourhan (Gesture and Speech, 1964-65, cf. ritual
and myth) close to the field of symbolic
anthropology. Consequently the
chapter abounds in references to how to counter the de-symbolization effect of
technology, akin to the same effect of money. There are further references to
need to offset the loss of educational symbolic-mythical processes and systems.
Beyond processes and systems the text is full with the adjective
"symbolic" or the lexeme symbol
applied to mediations, capital, schemes, creation, forms, relations, order,
culture, world, universe, constructions, dimensions, register, religious, and
production. One vivid example is given by the symbolic loss of initiation and
ritual for sexual approach, leading to rape
behavior. The reader may note that rape in our society is widely and ritually
condemned but seldom related to a search for why.
Human participation in symbolic
systems and the necessary internalization of values is seen as achieved in
narrow combination among the sensitive, the social, the technical, and the
religious, mutually consolidated by a narrow interaction between gesture and
speech (p. 160). Later on the author quotes Thomas
Robert Malthus concerning what wealth is or should be in political
economy: religion, morals, political and civil freedom, eloquence, educative and
pleasant conversations, music, dance, theater, and other services and qualities (p. 164) He also criticizes Karl
Marx for considering "in the
rationalist tradition" only formal and intellectual dimensions of the
"symbolic capital": law, political ideas, art, religion, while
neglecting the "social symbolic capital" and non-monetary practices
for the construction of social bonds and economic life (p. 171f.). In other
words, the reader gets the impression that the author regards
"symbolism" as encompassing everything and all grounds, in an analog
totalizing way as earlier undefined "systems" and later "design"
seems to encompass all human activity according to trends in academia. For
instance religion or, rather, theology that in history of universities was
considered the queen of sciences, becomes only one dimension among dozens of
others. So, the question that arises in this chapter may be seen as how to
design or redesign and implement symbolisms, well distinct from the present
proliferation of discourse and signs mediated by information and communication
technology that is, rather, a symptom of crisis
of symbolism. The reader hopes that all this will not result in a
"postmodernist" turn towards aestheticism and design where
aesthetics, often mentioned in a conjuring gratuitous combination with
"ethics") ultimately is supposed to replace theology as the queen of
sciences and everything else. It will turn out that book's author suggests that
his approach relies on Cassirer but also on Merleau-Ponty, while his passion
for the concept of "imaginary" that powers technology is understood
in the same sense as by Gilbert Durand.
The reader may note that the latter's "symbolic anthropology" is said
to have been influenced by Carl Jung but the controversies in which he has been
involved as thesis advisor of the militant anarchist Michel Gaucher,
and as teacher of the postmodern sociologist Michel
Maffesoli, in turn advisor of the famous Élizabeth
Tissier's thesis, indicate
important complications for the reader's judgment of the nature of the actual
influence of Jungian thought on postmodern "fringe" beliefs. As Paul
Bishop expresses it "Jung's intention was, however, to
explain the psychology behind such 'fringe' beliefs, not propagate them."
(New Humanist, 123:1, 2008.)
The breakdown of the symbolic texture
is further exemplified in the book's chapter X on politics vs. civilization. It
considers the social context and reactions to the hurricane
Katarina in the USA in 2005, as related to the
1900
Galveston hurricane considered to be to date the deadliest natural disaster ever to strike the United States.
The message is to point out the breakdown of the political and social
(symbolical?) texture of society as evidenced by the incapability of taking
preventive measures or confessing the impotence of technology. Despite the
relatively minor impact of Katarina in terms of human lives, the denial of the
sociopolitical and technical incapability to face improbable but evidently
possible disasters, i.e. to acknowledge that "nature exists, indeed"
(p. 185, cf. the "social construction of gender") results in the
search and appointment of scapegoats, in this case "government". In
this context the reader may appreciate some of the debate among ecologists with
reference to environmental forecasting, as in Daniel Borkin's article on "Science
and Soothsaying" and its
comments, which raise in the reader the suspicion that there are also other
scapegoats around: to pity all humanity (and incidentally our children) for the long term
effects of global warming and environmental degradation while many people are
suffering and dying now
of poverty, starvation and wars. Our book's author continues with other well
known cases of "ill-intentioned" people, terrorists and such,
justifying the increased police control and brutal treatment of brutalized
citizens, plus obviously brutal military international violence by, yes, the
very same government. At this point arises in the reader the thought that one
of the main drives of technology, to begin with historically, is for weapons
and war. The book does not touch upon the question of how to ensure peace,
beyond the obscure suggestion of producing new symbolic systems (see below) and
beyond seeing aggression as supported by scapegoat ideology, suggesting that
war itself is the result of the technological search for power. What is ignored
is the main mythical-symbolic, if not religious and Christian, scapegoat of
Jesus Christ, himself an icon for the "non-power" called for earlier
in the book.
In the following third part of the
book, however, it turns out that Christianity is not ignored. A massive amount
of the text of chapter XI (p. 189ff.) is dedicated to the incarnation of the
abstract logos, in theological terms that paradoxically follow the partly secularized
thought of three of the book's ideologically dominating scholars of industry
and technology: Jacques Ellul, Bernard Charbonneau and Ivan Illich.
Paradoxically, the author acknowledges here and in another place of the book
(p. 191, 254) that he, like the agnostic "postchristian" (but
hopefully not "postmodern"?) Charbonneau (p. 196) is neither
theologian nor believer, only aiming at understanding those three authors. He
rejects those expressions of Christianity and other religions that regard man's
aim as being to approach God in the sense of their own deification by means of the
liberation of the thinking rational spirit from the constrains of material
reality in general and the body or, rather, human flesh in particular. The
author's references to the unprecedented desincarnation of the word and thought
that is going on awakens in the reader an association to information technology
and virtual reality. It is this perverse dream that is seen to drive technology
to supposedly save or redeem man from the biblical fall from paradise.
As mentioned earlier this
problematization corresponds to the classical hubris
which, symptomatically meant abuse of power and concomitant overconfidence,
equivalent to self-deification, also illustrated in the Catholic newspaper The Remnant on Line under the title
"Deus
ex Machina (Soul of Technology, Sanctify Me)",
a satyre on the godly technology. The author goes on problematizing the
important concept of freedom with the purpose of showing that as in the example
of Christ incarnated it is not a question of acquiring power for the purpose of
doing whatever one happens to want, but rather to struggle in this earthly life
following the example of Christ (cf. the non mentioned Imitation of Christ).
At a certain point both liberally and socialistically oriented institutional
organizations, specialized technological knowledge, and industry, prevent the
incarnation of man leading to a moral and ecological degradation of our lives.
Resistance is only possible by means of the "love for life and the
striving for all forms of happiness offered by sensitive life" as well as
a by a kind of rural "carnal attachment to beauty" (p. 199f.). The
reader, as well as outright hedonists, may intuit here a tempting theoretical
bridge over to aestheticist postmodernism, a step that, for instance, is
clearly indicated by Michel Maffesoli's ambiguous "ethical aesthetics",
e.g. in his "In the Hollow of Appearances",
but still more explicitly in "In Praise of Sensitive Reason"
(translated titles) where description merges treacherously with prescription.
It may be suggestive to compare the imaginary of "the hollow" with
its probable source in Heidegger's own "empty" and
"nothing" in his essay "The
Origin of the Work of Art" (found e.g. in his Basic Writings) versus T.S Eliot's
poem The Hollow Men.
Ultimately it all recalls in my mind a (paradoxically godless) version of negative
theology and
a sort of Jungian collective
unconscious without its
empirical ground.
The book's descriptions of postmodern
society then merge with apparent prescriptions that are spiced with a
criticisms of a choice of catholically influenced, uncritical apologies of
faith in technological progress (p. 212f.). If nothing else this approach serves
as a tacit justification for the author's agnosticism, but in its conjunction
with the postmodern turns it tends to become a postmodern message. The appeals
to "incarnation" when divorced from Catholic teaching risk to turn
into an appeal to idolatry. "Flesh" is indeed a highly sensitive
issue in the Christian context of dangers of idolatry
and the more so in text written by an outspokenly unbelieving agnostic who
paradoxically theologizes about Jesus Christ through the whole chapter. The
question arises whether the "flesh" itself does not incur the danger
of "false concreteness of pseudo-percepts" (p. 203) as it eventually
appears in a sort of phenomenological apotheosis of the flesh in the appendix
at the end of the book (p. 253). And this is just after the anti-climax
of the book's final words, consisting of an imperative for man to cultivate
what Friedrich
Nietzsche's superman called "the sense of
the earth" (p. 252, cf. Zarathustra's Prologue).
It would take too far indeed to develop here the hypothesis that the Christian
solution of the question of the flesh as related to incarnation is represented
by the theological and psychological interpretations of the
"concrete" sacrament of Eucharist:
Swedish readers may notice especially the statements by Anders
Piltz in Radio Sweden's program "Teologiska
Rummet" 22 April 2012. Other readers
can read about sacrament,
and about "fleshy" ritual in the context of myth vs.
ritual, without implying that religions are
myths, whatever one should understand as myth.
Some legitimate Christian and catholic
messages in the text, however, remain in the form of genuine appeals against
any dissociation between means and ends. The ends must be incorporated not only in its
effects but also in the agent and its means. The means must also be purposeful,
all this amounting to a primacy of life with respect to action (p. 205f.)
Several such thoughts are borrowed from the ("anarchist") catholic
Jacques Ellul, but the reader may ponder further, upon the fact that they are
an integrated part of the official Catholic Catechism, esp. 1752 ff. They are also founded
in scientifically developed form in West Churchman's The Design
of Inquiring Systems (chap. 3 on "the anatomy of goal seeking").
This conception of systems including its "pragmatist" appeal to act
has nothing to do with the Ivan Illich's criticized "age of systems"
or "professionalized design" that refers to the banal,
sense-based "design turn" that succeeded the banal versions of the
"systems turn" of the fifties, while ignoring the core meaning of
design as addressed by Edmund Husserl in The Crisis of European Sciences (second part, 9). In this context it becomes
important to understand the "Churchmanian" preferred orientation
inspired by William James's pragmatism (contrasted to John Dewey's, common in design-circles, and Charles S. Peirce, in their relation to phenomenology, ref. Études
Phénoménologiques 1989, No. 9-10). Unfortunately such a relation to
pragmatism is neither hinted nor explored in the book. It would indicate
alternative ways for phenomenology and the integration of the book's criticism
of modern science with new approaches to the problems of modernity, and
postmodernity. It would avoid the recourse to what some readers of the book may
perceive as a pseudo-Christian "mysticism of the flesh" permeating
the conclusion and the appendix that follow the last chapter XII.
The
last chapter XII of the book is in part a summary of earlier insights, starting
with the observation of the dynamics of speedy growth and sprawling of new
interrelated branches of technology, which require continuous and unpredictable
needs for innovation and change. The author presents also some by now
"classical" findings about the enormous "information
explosion" of numbers of scientific journals and articles all over the
world. Reality gets always more complicated than foreseen, requiring societal
changes at an increasing rate, with
actions and organizational structures that are continuously left
"unfinished". The desperate call for predictability is accompanied by
repeated denial of "the real" (and a plunge into the
"virtual", the reader may think) This requires increasingly severe
"democratically lawful" guarantees for public order (cf. Alexis de Tocqueville's problematization of democracy, the
reader also may think), and security measures that are supposed to prevent
disastrous global accidents or sabotages by creating (an artificial, virtual)
predictability. This includes computer-supported policing and digital
surveillance of the general public who willingly and gradually surrenders its
privacy, seen to carry negligible weight in the context. Unpredictability feeds
irresponsibility and haphazard behavior in face of harnessed but dangerous,
technologically created and accumulated, natural energy. This is exemplified by
the terrorism of the Oklahoma City bombing, followed by the September 11 attacks. All these processes cause a
cultural disorganization and a perversion of values and spiritual traditions,
as they are called in the book. In the middle of all this, researchers in
general and university researchers in particular are described as driven by the
expectation of profits but also by the mirage of career, exchange of favors,
prestige, influence, and will to power, while their sense of responsibility is
gradually weakened.
What
to do? Starting with this chapter begin to appear the author's increasingly
explicit suggestions and prescriptions about what to do, often if now always in
the form of statements or Kantian-like tacit categorical imperatives that
initially may pass unperceived with respect to their quality of imperatives.
"It
takes much time to evaluate the consequences of our actions", "it
takes time to learn to use any technology advisedly",
"it must take the time" (to
evaluate and learn), "it is vital to impose a slower rate of technological
change." Or more specifically: "facing the impossibility of
suspending technological innovation, if taking our time is a duty, then we must
instrumentalize it in the form of law, a moratorium, in order for us to have the time to produce the
symbolic cultural resources and the adoption of strong ethical guidelines"
(my italics). Or, "more urgent than technical innovation is to resolve on moral and political bases the
social and environmental problems by two centuries of techno-scientific and
industrial progress" (my free
translation and emphasis, pp. 240ff.) For a reader it may seem obvious what a
Marxist versus a liberal or a libertarian,
versus a pious (not "fundamentalist") Christian would start objecting
to in such a program, and the question would pass to deal with what it means,
and what are the limitations of, the process of producing symbolic cultural capital. This is the focus of the final
conclusions and the appendix that consequently terminate the book.
In
the concluding chapter the author dwells upon the possibility to invent new venues
for a non dehumanizing development of technology, after he has found that
political projects have failed, such as socialisms, communisms, fascisms,
nationalisms, and religious fundamentalisms (that seem to be equated to
religions). To begin with, for every innovation it should be required to proceed to a careful examination of long term
costs including futurely foreclosed choices that are often underestimated, and
the short term benefits that are often presented as necessities and are
overestimated. To provide oneself with the means to choose requires much
knowledge but also "political and institutional inventions" (the
reader may think about Karl Marx). But this is difficult because modern man is
unconsciously fascinated by the values of power, novelness, and quickness.
Furthermore, technological modernity is seen to stand in unsuspected harmony
with religion and metaphysics despite the apparent ruptures declared by
positivists and progressivists. This is so since technology is often considered
by certain theology to be a legitimate way offered by God (the godly spirit of
reason) to repair consequences of the original human fall and ascend by
transcending the limits of low materiality. A reader may note that theology's
position in this respect as in fact ambiguous was noted long ago in a book
edited by Carl Mitcham and Jim Grote, Theology
and Technology. Curiously it turns out that in his conclusion the author's
language makes recourse to the concept of power that he per se condemns, in
order "to provide oneself with the means to choose", depending upon
who is oneself and whose choices. It becomes a matter of "mastering
technical innovation", "submit it to choices", or "regain
self-control". The reader ponders: it is indeed difficult for man,
especially Western man, to renounce to the language of power as much as to
renounce to power itself. Possibly this is one of the reasons why secularized
man does not like Christianity, as little as he likes to follow the apparently
absurd non-power recipe of the already mentioned Imitation of Christ, or why he prefers to talk about
power to subdue power into non-power, or as in Scandinavian countries to
paradoxically and "Protestantly" counter the so called Law of
Jante,
rather than to talk about Christian love or charity. Or, then, Westerners look
for attractive foreign religions or Buddhism, which in their misunderstood and
oversimplified form apparently preach a sort of easy salvation without painful
sacrifices or final judgements.
At this point the author finds the
indispensable need for what he calls a demythologization of technology (p.
249). The reader may note that the loosely defined demythologization has a
standing in the theology of (the unmentioned) Rudolf Bultmann, or perhaps in
other unclear sources, but the statement is rather paradoxical in view of the
book's initial commitment to the necessary role of the imaginary in all human
thought. The paradoxical question then arises in the reader, about which (non
mythological?) imaginary would direct the process of demythologization that for
many religious people of the world, and for Christians in particular is the
domain of religion itself. In another context of analysis of so called
political correctness I did write a review
of a book by Howard
Schwartz on organizational psychology that
includes a suggestion of how one can see Christianity as performing a synthesis
of myths that correspond to what our book here calls production of a new
symbolic system, addressing phenomena of "virtual existences" in
chapter IV of our book reviewed here. Our author continues, however, with a
gradual increase of emphasis of references to "symbolization". Man's
relation to the world is not only intellectual and operative but also sensitive
and symbolic. There are not only technical and intellectual dimensions of
freedom but also symbolic. The relation to the world is not only technical and
intellectual but also affective (undefined, but assumedly related to the
symbolic and the sensitive). There are sensitive and aesthetic dimensions in
our relation to the world. The use of tools and power have always been
humanized, integrated into the human world by means of symbolic production, in
a symbolic order. In a couple of pages (p. 250f.) we find the previously
mentioned further reference to symbolic world, symbolic universe, symbolic
constructions, unconsciously symbolic production, symbolic culture, symbolic
capital, symbolic schemata, symbolic creation and, again, symbolic production
for a new symbolic universe. Without going to the multiple implicit sources of
thought about symbolism and phenomenological carnalism the reader may not even
able to try to grasp what all this symbolism is and how it will solve the
technological problem. But the author categorically
states that its taking into consideration the carnal dimension of human
existence can ground the concern for imposing
another slower temporality, or a moratorium to technical change.
In the final Appendix, the
author seemingly offers an apology for his approach as a defense against the
criticism he expect will be directed towards his emphasis on theological interpretations
of incarnation as an introduction to the flesh. He fears "that such notion
of flesh smells too much of sacristy". Indeed, one may wonder why the
reader of the book is expected to respect the argument of Christ's incarnation
when the author himself, once again in this appendix (p. 254) repeats that he
is not a (Christian) believer. In the apparently unconscious impasse of
bypassing this paradox the author suddenly endorses some quotations from Edmund
Husserl and Maurice Merleau-Ponty who consequently must be supposed to bear the
burden of the whole theoretical framework of the book with respect to
what-to-do. For the systems-oriented reader of our reviewed book
"what-to-do" is mainly the question of implementation that West Churchman long ago had conceived in terms
of mutual
understanding and
later developed in terms of the confluence of the roles of
researcher-decisionmaker-client in the so called Singerian inquiring systems
(see my homepage's Index
of "Inquiring Systems", keyword "implementation"), or what today, as we saw
above, corresponds to the aims of the capability approach mentioned earlier.
This has been the object of an article of mine on
the Systems
Approach to Design, and Inquiring Systems. But the book launches instead a Husserlian philosophical
differentiation between body and flesh. The flesh is further defined as
suggested by Merleau-Ponty as the "animated body" and the author
boldly claims (in my free edited translation): "The flesh is the indestructible
foundation that feeds our thoughts, up to the most abstract. It is a founding
and paradoxical reality that is characterized by moral metaphors. Thus the flesh interacts with a primordial symbolism as understood
by Ernst Cassirer, i.e. forms that are developed through language, religion,
myth, art and science."
The
author then writes the following last words in the appendix, which indicate
that he seems to have had a foreboding that he must preventively counter the
reader's perception that there is much of a "mystical irrationalism".
The question is what will the effect be upon the reader of what may appear to
him more of a disclaimer: the author claims namely that the above references in
his appendix are sufficient "to
show, without tipping over to a mystical irrationalism, that human reason can
build upon the fruitful notion of flesh."
In my view the main valuable message of this rich book about the essence of technological thinking and its consequences is contained in the first two parts and in its relating the subject matter to the European, and especially French cultural sphere. The book is a veritable tour de force. It is saturated with many names that are not sufficiently known in the Anglo-Saxon world, and are not completely covered by bibliographic data in the references scattered through the notes of the book which, as in the French publishing tradition, unfortunately lacks both a word-index. The realm of English language is all too often presumed by Anglo-Saxon researchers to be auto-sufficient but it would profit of more translations from foreign languages. The author seems to have been most strongly influenced by known and less known French names like Jacques Ellul, Jean Brun, Bernard Charbonneau. Gilbert Hottois, Dominique Janicaud, and Michel Henry, (Incarnation: A Philosophy of the Flesh) complete the list of French personalities who appear often referenced in the book, besides other Europeans who are more common in Anglo-Saxon literature, like Martin Heidegger, Hans Jonas, Alexandre Koyr, and Ivan Illich. This does not mean that Anglo-Saxon and especially American research is ignored. For instance, a tribute is given to such research: from a theoretical standpoint by Carl Mitcham who co-edited the impressive book on Theology and Technology, and from the practical standpoint by several authors who have studied high risk technologies and disasters (p. 65f, 179). The philosophical basis of the book seems to stand ultimately on the phenomenology of the (for me) problematically elusive Maurice Merleau-Ponty (The Visible and the Invisible), and the related Ernst Cassirer (his Philosophy of Symbolic Forms), while an American philosopher of technology like Albert Borgmann is not considered, possibly because he thinks along the same philosophical "Heideggerian" lines as other referenced French authors by whom the author is indeed influenced. The American reader is also kept wondering what relation the work has, if any, with other similar approaches in terms of "flesh", "body", and possibly phenomenology, such as by Mark Johnson (e.g. The Body in the Mind), his co-author George Lakoff ( in Philosophy in the Flesh), and Francisco Varela, Evan Thompson and Eleanor Rosch (The Embodied Mind), or the Italian Giulio Angioni (in Il sapere della Mano, i.e. The Hand's Knowledge).
The last chapters of the book
regarding a supposed conclusion or implementation culminate with what I
perceived as an anti-climax.
I concede, however, that this may testify my incapability to grasp the inherent
implications of Cassirer's work on symbolism and the conceptualization of the
phenomenology of the flesh by Merleau-Ponty's, and of phenomenology in general.
I did not see clear theoretical connections either to the similar works in the European
or in the Anglo-Saxon sphere as mentioned above, works that I have been
skeptical about all the same. Even when I see theoretical connections, like
with the phenomenology of Giulio Angioni's, I wonder about the absent role,
there, of Cassirer's symbolism. The credibility of our reviewed book's
theoretical approach is undermined to begin with by the use of weird
imperatives that by far do not seem to be grounded as well as the famous
Kantian categorical imperative, which in a theological perspective is by itself
very controversial. As a one-time detailed account I share here my annotations
about (besides many pages with uses of the socio-politically sensitive use of
the pronoun "we" all over the text) the pages of the book containing
a-political and a-religious, more and less tacit imperatives in various
semantic forms: pages 7, 11, 104, 138, 157, 227, 236, 240-242, 245, 250, 252.
Their proliferation is only, and vastly, exceeded by the use of words with the
lexeme symbol. Obviously such
vocabulary of imperatives does not take into account what the author himself
quotes (p. 158) from Carl Mitcham regarding the risk of incontinence
understood as willing evil despite of knowing the good, while Mitcham probably
had in mind "For
I do not understand my own actions. For I do not do what I want, but I do the
very thing I hate" (Romans 7:15 ESV). And how about that? What or who would be of help,
in the middle of today' confusion about human will and ethics?
This leads to what I think is most
important: that despite the book's emphasis on the Christian doctrine of the
incarnation as well as on life and flesh, the famous teachings of the Christian
philosophy
of the body (controversial
among traditionalist
catholics) are ignored. What is also ignored is
also their integration in the encyclical Evangelium Vitae
(1995) on the value and inviolability of human life. It may turn out that
Merleau-Ponty's phenomenological differentiation between body and flesh has
much to do with the theological (and Carl Jung's) differentiation between body,
soul and spirit (cf. another essay
on this). And Carl Jung's relation to Paul Tillich's
Heideggerian existentialism as it appears in J.P Dourley's Trinitarian Models and Human
Integration also offers
problematic insights, as they are offered also by studies of relation between Cartesian
philosophy and the flesh, from
analytic-psychological perspective of "incarnation". Scholars of
Rudolf Steiner point out that even his anthroposophical work with its very
special interpretation of Christianity has a refined analysis of the issue as
in his Christianity as a Mystical Fact
(GA 8) and The Gospel of St. Luke (GA
114) as related to the resurrection
of Jesus, with a core text found as the The Meaning of Easter.
Valdemar
Setzer has written a comprehensive anthroposophical
essay on the subject. That, if anything,
would at least acknowledge the strife that with Christianity has being going
for at least two thousand years for the upgrade and rescue of flesh and life,
something that does not seem to be acknowledged in the book's endorsed
philosophy of the flesh.
When this is said I must emphasize that all references to religion and
especially Christianity in this review, including occasional references to the
Bible, do not imply a doctrinaire preaching. My position is that an
intellectually honest analysis of the problems considered here cannot be
pursued on the basis of only Heidegger or Cassirer, explaining away as crazy,
irrational or irrelevant the historical and present intellectual debates about
the religious commitments of the clear majority of humanity that did not and
does not subscribe to a complex, problematic atheism,
or a simpler agnosticism.
As an amusingly significant curiosity I will mention that a childhood friend of
mine who in his teenage had begun to express atheistic thoughts was told by his
Italian father that no objections would be raised by the family so long he
espoused atheism only after having read and understood the Summa
Theologica by Thomas Aquinas.
An alternative later text that illustrates neglected complexities is La
Querelle de l'Athéisme [The Dispute of Atheism], a French
collection of translated German texts by J.-G. Fichte
(from Werke; Band V,
Berlin, 1971) in consideration of relations between Fichte and Husserl (cf.
Denis Fisette, pdf-download)
and the Heidegger of our reviewed book (cf. Alfred Denker, "Der junge
Heidegger und Fichte", from Fichte-Studien,
13, 1997, pdf-download).
And this brings us back to both
phenomenology and symbolism. Regarding phenomenology I adduce Karl
Lwith's portrait at the Goethe Institute
written by Berndt Mayerhofer, and Lwith's famous statements quoted by John
Macquarrie in Heidegger and Christianity (p.
6) taken from Lwith's From Hegel to
Nietzsche (trans. by D.E. Green, 1967, p. 207). I will never forget my
reading it many years ago, namely that Heidegger's philosophy "is in its very essence a theology without
God". And, as Macquarrie observes (p.70f.) "we might blame
Heidegger himself for never having developed an ethical side to his
philosophy...he consistently avoided ethical questions...the ethical question
is passed by." (I think it is really so, except for some
inconsequential statements in his Letter
on Humanism, found in Basic
Writings, and see below about "values" and blasphemy
against Being.) Or, as Mayerhofer expresses it for the Goethe
Institute: Lwith (a contemporary student of Heidegger) at least noted that
"modernity, oriented to a this-worldly goal [cf.
our book's flesh, my note] and a philosophy of history obsessed with the idea
of a successive approximation of this goal [even if framed as survival or
peace, my note], depends upon theology or the theological view of history as a
redemptive process. This idea originates in the biblical belief in salvation
and ends with the ҳecularizing of its eschatological modelӮ And I would say that despite Husserl, and Martin Heidegger, it is
Friedrich Nietzsche behind them who is the representative philosophical
"father" of it all about flesh and earth. In this sense the book is
an outpost for Nietzschean thought and it explains its seemingly paradoxical
pulling ahead of this sort of Christianity.
A better understanding of the book's theology of the flesh revealed as a
theology without God beyond or behind wholesale superficial references to Merleau-Ponty would also have
dampened the final anti-climax at reader's meeting the flesh as a sort of
conclusion at the end of the text. Such an understanding is offered if one
collates the book's terminology against phenomenological vocabulary as related
to Heidegger. It turns out that the book's flesh corresponds to what Michel
Henry in his work on barbarism calls simply "life". Life corresponds
in turn to Heidegger's famous "Being", also sometimes referred to as
"Presence", recalling the likewise obscurely conceived presence that
is (in the light of our reviewed book) paradoxically adduced in the
"post-literate future of body-based communication" of high-tech
human-computer interaction such as in the essay (pdf-download) "Presence
as a Dimension of Communications".
That is: Flesh=Life=Presence=Being. (For being as presence see D.F. Krell's
introduction to Martin Heidegger: Basic
Writings, 1978, and Henry, p. 125). That it is a matter of theology
without God becomes evident in the awkward treatment of the central question of
ethics, or the outright disappearance of ethical discourse in even more
ambitious approaches to philosophy of flesh as medium, such as Helena Dahlberg's book (2013, in
Swedish) Vad
är Kött? [What is Flesh?]
that was preceded by her PhD dissertation The
Weight of the Body: The Question of Flesh and Human Being
(2011, pdf-English summary here.)
The book has been for me the best explanation, better than in Cérézuelle's book
reviewed here, of the emphasis on flesh: it is seen as the limit, transition or
medium between the subject and
object as originated in Cartesian
dualism. Those who do not read Swedish may
consult the list of related works listed among the references that appear on Dahlberg's
home page. Otherwise there are some valuable
book reviews, which summarize and clarify that author's conception of flesh as
related to Merleau-Ponty, such as one review in the Swedish magazine Tidningen
Kulturen (23 dec. 2013) and
one in the periodical Arbetaren
(7/ 15 Feb. 2014, p. 10.) In the latter, the initiated author of the review, Axel Andersson,
observes that "the flesh" becomes almost a magical and undefined
substance such as humanism's desintegrating "human being", not to
mention the indefiniteness of what the "medium" and
"communication" (and ethics) is about and by whom in the context of
such desintegrating human being. That is an indefiniteness I already had met in
an early essay of mine (1991) on Humanistic
computer science.
Because of reasons of space and focus I have moved the more detailed treatment
of this issue into a separate text betitled: Ethics in Technology, and Theology of
the Flesh, which includes
references to feminist mysticism of flesh-related "touching" (reference
to the strange terminology by Karen Barad),
and Michel Henry's approach based on the philosophy of Heidegger who together
with Ernst Cassirer (see below) influenced the author of our book, Daniel
Cérézuelle. The conclusion is that the application of Martin Heidegger's
phenomenological thought and its vocabulary contributes to a hidden, systematic
neglect of ethics in both technological research and in research on technology.
The question of symbolism in its
relation to flesh may be the most important one raised in the book. If one
still does not want or dare to relate committedly to theology and religion, an
alternative would be to start considering seriously the "imaginary"
emphasized in the book by means of in-depth studies of the Greek myth of
Daedalus as master craftsman such as the one published in 1975 by the Hellenist
Franoise Frontisi-Ducroux, Daedalus: Mythology of the craftsman
in ancient Greece (translated
title.) This is, however part of another major question about the
psychological, and still more the sociopsychological aspect of mythology that
in our book is subsumed under or reduced to "the imaginary". My own
bias leads me to follow further this path towards Carl Jung who historically
has already been researched in his relation to Cassirer. Before addressing this
question I wish to note that the relation between our reviewed book's Cassirer
and Heidegger as one main origin of it all is mentioned in Mark Lilla's review
considered above. He recalls (in his part 1, Ménage à
Trois, p. 13) that in 1929 Heidegger was invited to Davos,
Switzerland, to debate the respected neo-Kantian Cassirer, "and so
successfully trounced him in the eyes of young people in the audience that the
mantle of leading German philosopher was unofficially bestowed upon him
there." For me this shows first of all Heidegger's rhetorical power among
those who a few years later would likewise appreciate the rhetorical power of
nazist leaders.
Jung's relation to Cassirer is considered in Paul Bishop's essay noted earlier
(Thinker: Carl Jung).
Works like the ones by Joy Schaverien and
Petteri Pietikainen or Paul Bishop can be, symptomatically in
respect to the religious issue, misunderstood to reduce Jung to Cassirer,
something that is the core of our problem, since what Jung did was to take both
religion and the psychological in social psychology in an extremely serious
way, far from regarding religion as only one item in a list of human activities.
This is so even if Jung was not theologically approved by the Catholic
establishment, probably because suspected of reducing religion to mythology and
archetypes, as Cassirer reduces religion to foundational symbolic forms. I do
not agree that Jung does this, based on my own studies of Jung's collected
works, with his careful distinction between religion and psychology, his
archetypal God in the human "Self"
that others programmatically have tried to reduce to "socialization",
and his own profession of
knowledge of God that today is in
turn controversially secularized,
if yet in anthroposophical
terms. See for instance what Jung writes in the context of Christianity (CW 5,
§ 106f., p. 75f.): "To the degree that the modern mind is passionately
concerned with anything and everything rather than religion, religion and its
prime object - original sin - have mostly vanished into the unconscious. That
is why, today, nobody believes in either. People accuse psychology of dealing
in squalid fantasies, and yet even a cursory glance at ancient religions and
the history of morals should be sufficient to convince them of the demons
hidden in the human soul. This disbelief in the devilishness of human nature
goes hand in hand with the blank incomprehension of religion and its meaning
[...] Through centuries of educational training, Christianity subdued the
animal instincts of antiquity and of the ensuing ages of barbarism to the point
where a large amount of instinctual energy could be set free for the building
of civilization." In view of Cassirer I would add "building of
civilization and so called
construction of symbolic worlds",
symbolic worlds that, however, contrary to Cassirer, do not include or
substitute Christianity, and there lies the great misunderstanding in the application
of Cassirer. Whoever wants to appreciate Jung's approach to religion and
Christianity, constrasting it to Cassirer's, may consult, for instance, the
word index of his Two Essays in Analytical
Psychology (Collected Works, vol. 7) for entries such as religion, religious, God/god(s), Christ,
Christian, Christianity, and church.
A hint about the "imaginary" of Cassirer in this respect may be
obtained from encyclopedic reviews more easily than from his demanding works. The Blackwell
Encyclopedia of Modern Christian Thought states e.g. that Cassirer describes religion as one among several modes of human
self-definition (whatever that definition means, apart from unnecessary
gods) including art, language and science, which use symbols to form
experience, and that he sees the relationship between myth and religion as
inextricable: they both originate in the "feeling of the indestructible
unity of life" and in the fear of death as a threat to that unity. Please
note: life and life again. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy notes that Cassirer's
philosophy of symbolic forms is concerned above all with the mythical view of
the world lying at the most primitive level of all cultural forms. These forms
are supposed to have an independent status and foundational role (whatever a
foundational role is, apart from unnecessary gods). They lie at a deeper,
autonomous level of spiritual life which then, by a "dialectical
development process" gives rise to the more sophisticated forms like
religion, art, language and theoretical sciences. That is, once again a "theology
without God" related to the Lebensphilosophie
and Heidegger where religion, thanks to philosophy becomes just one item among
various possible human activities. As pointed out by C.S Lewis in Mere Christianity (chap. 24), the
impersonal, non-anthropomorphic god that is substituted by some other smart
word other than God becomes less than a person, and recalls Nietzsche's
superman.
I perceive that "life"
in the traditions close to our reviewed book becomes a supreme concept, as in
our reviewed book where the author seemingly further equates it to flesh. These
"notions" of life, flesh, earth or rather the strife between earth
and world, and such, usurp the place of God himself and most theologians would
call it idolatry. Religion suddenly finds itself as one item of a list of
"modes of human self-definition" besides art, language, and science.
In the above text of my review of the book we also saw unproblematized
quotations like "religion, morals, political and civil freedom, eloquence,
educative and pleasant conversations, music, dance, theater, and other
services and qualities". Or
"only formal and intellectual dimensions of the "symbolic
capital": law, political ideas, art, religion, while neglecting the
'social symbolic capital'". Or, again "the flesh interacts with a primordial symbolism as understood
by Ernst Cassirer, i.e. forms that are developed through language, religion,
myth, art and science." These
excerpts uncover the real problem of religion being relegated to a service or
quality, or to a formal-intellectual dimension of the social symbolic capital,
and it is consistent with how Cassirer, in the previous paragraph, is said to
consider religion. And, for that matter, it is consistent with our whole modern
or postmodern secularized philosophy divorced from religion in general and from
Christianity in particular.
It is possible that the project of the
book to harness technology in the Western setting can only be pursued by means
of a revival of Christianity and that there is no shortcut like, in the book's
language, producing or manufacturing new "symbolic systems". It will
be more of a maintenance of the Christian symbolic system. Earlier it was
called evangelization
and missionary
work. Today it is being done by the second
or third world that send their own catholic priests in mission to Western
countries, e.g. from India to Sweden. The alternative would be to launch new
religions, to be compared with, say Marxism,
Kant's religion of
reason, positivism's religion
of humanity, Heidegger's
religion without god, some "-isms, and such. And some would now like to
claim: also a phenomenological religion of the flesh. But it will not help to
reject summarily God's ten commandments, replacing them with home-made
imperatives or exclaiming, like Heidegger, that only a god can still save us. Consider the rhetorically yielding,
and inconsequentially passivating quotation of Heidegger's passus:
"Philosophy will not be able
to bring about a direct change of the present state of the world. This is true
not only of philosophy but of all merely human meditations and endeavors. Only a god can still save us [my
italics]. I think the only possibility of salvation left to us is to prepare
readiness, through thinking and poetry, for the appearance of the god or for
the absence of the god during the decline; so that we do not, simply put, die
meaningless deaths, but that when we decline, we decline in the face of the
absent god... We cannot get him to come
by thinking. At best we can prepare the readiness of expectation."
(From Der Spiegel interview,
but there are alternative
translations).
Disregarding that (if the
transcription and translation are faithful) it is matter of "a god"
and not God, in theological terms it is symptomatic that Heidegger speaks
indeed like a
prophet, and does not mention prayer, and
does not seem to be aware of the problem implied by the Bible ending indeed
with the Apocalypse.
Since my own field of research has
been information science I conclude by following the theological thread of the
possible place of religion in it. I mean that information science in the age of
computers has synthesized classical logic, mathematics and statistics, and has
come to merge with computer science and capitalistic economy in various modes
that are supposed to match the field of informatics. At the same time we have
already seen that modern technology is inextricably tied to science supported
by modern mathematics and logic. For our purposes we can merge logic and
mathematics since their relation has been object of dispute that remain obscure
for most non specialists. My point here is to emphasize the fundamental
importance of understanding the meaning of mathematization of science and
technology, in general and the increasing computerization of society in
particular.
I am not sure that today's most
popular approach, such as Husserl's concerning Galilei in philosophy of logic and mathematics
developed in the second part of his earlier mentioned The Crisis of European Sciences (
8-9), or an analog approach by Rudolf Steiner
in Origins of Natural Science (GA 326),
is the most fortunate one. I like to suggest that such an investigation should not start with a natural-science
framework such as the one presented by Eugene Wigner
in The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics
in the natural sciences (in Communications in Pure and Applied
Mathematics, vol. 13, No. 1, February 1960). A less detailed but broader
framework is suggested by a French sociologist of technology working close to
the tradition of the author of our book: Alain Gras,
founder of a Center for Studies of Technology, Knowledge and Practices CETCOPRA,
in chapter IV of his Fragility of Power (my
translation of the title) where he discusses the "enigma of the false
Galilean liberation". Let's be more specific. He notes tragic
misunderstandings regarding the position of the Catholic church with respect to
Galilei: "Galilei innovates also in an area previously reserved for
theology and ethics" (p. 129f). But the most ambitious approach I know is
that by the French "dean" of philosophers of science Alexandre
Koyr who, for instance, in his Studies of the History of
Philosophical Thought (my
translation of the title) writes that in the Newtonian world, it is not
man,
but God who is the measure of things. Newton's successors were able to forget
this, they thought that they did not need the God hypothesis, but hey were
wrong. Deprived of its divine support, the Newtonian world proved to be
unstable and precarious. He recalls that positivist historians are accustomed
to insist on Galileo's and Newton's experimental, empiricist, phenomenalist
sides. But this implies a waiver of the search for causes, in favor of the search for laws. This means the removal of the question: why? and its replacement by the question: how? (p.264). As reader, my intuition is that it is not strange
that in the absence of a why and of
the top of it, given by God, it becomes man's increased temptation to use the
mathematically described laws or hows in order to reach his own whys, in their new sense of his own
goals. Similar complementing insights are suggested by Koyr in his Studies of
the History of Scientific Thought (e.g. p. 322) and a professional
mathematical treatment of the problem is summarized in Walter P. Van Stigt's
account of "The rejected parts of Brouwer's dissertation on the
foundations of mathematics" (Historia Mathematica, vol. 6, 1979.)
But as for the previous studies mentioned here there is no place for a relation
to God or ethics and religion in our reviewed book, except for reducing God to
his incarnation, leading into an opaque metaphysics of the flesh. And
Heidegger's own contribution in this area (Modern Science, Metaphysics and Mathematics,
in his Basic Writings) does not add anything substantial to the
above.
In accord with the criticism contained in our reviewed book, the idea is to understand what is lost in a mathematical-logical approach to reality, given that nowadays it is all too clear what is gained, or supposed to be gained by means of technology in general and information technology in particular. In a poetic fashion this loss is described with great rhetoric power by mathematical physicist Helena Granström in her article in Svenska Dagbladet (in Swedish, 23 March 2014) about the latest evidence of gravitational waves in the infant universe. Her phenomenological approach does not allow, however, an inquiry into the "why" of the loss of ethics in modern science such as informatics as depicted in chapter VIII. Indeed, what happens with the computerization of society may be analog, if not in principle the same as with the mathematization of nature, where the malleable part of "reality" if forced into a logical-mathematical frame while the rest is ignored for the purpose of "efficacy". The phenomenon overlaps with what in Churchman's dialectical systems theory is sometimes called efficiency in contrast to effectiveness and with what the French philosopher-sinologist Franois Jullien studied in his Treatise on Efficacy. I studied the relation between the two approaches in an article that was eventually co-edited and published under the title East and West of Information Systems (1998). The efficacy of the general computerization of human interactions in a social environment is apparently increasing since they are still more malleable than the "given" physical nature. So, even disadvantaged, sick and old people are forced to push buttons, touch screens or handle keypads if they are to communicate (via mobile phones? Facebook?, Twitter?) with absent younger relatives or with medical emergency services.
As I have written elsewhere,
this may also be gradually obvious in the field of HCI (human-computer
interaction) when considering
that ongoing progressive computerization of society and of social interaction
violently forces humans
to (attempt to) adapt their more or less unconscious mental
models and behavior
to preconceived computerized structures. Such phenomena can be exemplified and
perceived as problems in the use of computers, particularly in problems of
human-computer interactions. Swedish readers can appreciate one best
description of how computer technology "rapes" the minds of citizens
in Anna-Lena Laurén's article "App,
app, app - det börjar likna Bolsjevism!"
[App, app, app - it begins to resemble Bolshevism!" (Dagens Nyheter 14 October
2018) and the follow-up by Ylva Hasselberg "Hejda
digitalbolsjevismen" [Stop the
digital Bolshevism] (Dagens
Nyheter 23 December 2018). See also the description of bugs
such as in the ticket system of Stockholm's public transportation, (En bugg
i SL:s biljettsystem, i.e. A bug in the ticket system of Stockholm's
Transportation, in Swedish language, Metro-Stockholm, 22 Dec.
2015.) It becomes more a question of forcing
human thought, trust and behavior, relinquishing self-reliance, into anonymous
structures that are required for the functioning of computer software and
hardware as much as supposedly for humans'
purposes. These are just a few examples that give the idea of what is
being achieved by means of the new social order and of coercive policing
measures that gradually dismantle the texture of daily life, privacy, human
rights and democratic freedom under the per se reasonable "pretext"
of cost reduction, economic prevention of accidents, sabotages, and terrorism,
as explained and expanded in our reviewed book.
And finally let's perform a light
"test" and apply our insights to the following "case
study", a research project in informatics aimed at increasing the level of
human engagement and involvement in the use of electronic computer products. In
March 2012 a Swedish university announced two
fellowships for PhD graduate study
in the area of Human-Computer
Interaction/Interaction Design. The text explained
among other things that the special DEIT
project presented on an early occasion
dealt with "design of engaging information technology" (DEIT),
implying that information technology (IT) is typically designed to do things
for its users: to make life more convenient, to automate or ease tasks, to
allow us to carry out tasks more efficiently, to free us from geographical
constraints, and to save time. Rooted in contemporary thinking from the
philosophy of technology, DEIT however argues that a common denominator among
successful IT today is the tendency to do the exact opposite. Successful
technologies, instead, tend to engage rather than disengage both mind and body;
they require effort, patience, and skill; and they help shape new relations
between humans, artifacts, and the world. They are designed to increase, not
decrease, the level of human engagement and involvement. The larger goal of the
DEIT research program is said to be the development of a new design philosophy
for information technology around the concepts of human engagement,
involvement, and embodiment. It is remarkable how the semantics of
salesmanship, both in business and research, can suddenly launch the term involvement, as a better substitute
and renewal of the earlier worn out interaction,
which in turn had seldom if ever been defined as in
"action" vs. "response" (cf. R.L. Ackoff
& F.E.
Emery, On
Purposeful Systems, p.
25 ff., 160 ff.) A later video-complement
describing the project specified that it would foster "pleasant digital
ecology" shifting the focus of product development from the pure
functionality and efficiency valued in working places to the needs and desires
of its users in everyday life, i.e. that which, for instance, "makes grown
up men play silly games on their mobile phones." All this may recall in
some reader's mind analog trends announced by some other
researcher in
"socio-cultural computing" and "user engagement", expressed
as follows: emphasis on
emotional, intimate, and embodied experiences that contribute to the broader
agenda of feminist human-computer interaction; focusing on intimate
interactions, designing for emotion, embodied collaboration in virtual spaces,
and the application of critical and cultural theories for developing
concept-driven strategies. Let us test whether the book reviewed here helps to
evaluate such trends in research claims.
What is engagement and involvement,
or, for that matter the alternative, academically more sophisticated presence, (once that apparently the
earlier fashion
word interaction
is no longer the main issue), put against our background? Yes, it would foster
"pleasant digital ecology" shifting the focus of product development
from the pure functionality and efficiency valued in working places to the
needs and desires of its users in everyday life, i.e. that which, for instance,
"makes grown up men play silly games on their mobile phones." A
test-run on Google indicates that motivation and engagement are most often
found as synonyms in psychology of education, and in business contexts such as
human resources and leadership or marketing, both possibly merged in studies
such as on digital
computer games. Long time ago,
studying for my major in psychology (at Lund university) I perceived motivation
psychology, not to mention
"emotions", as saturated with a chaos of ambiguous ethical questions,
something that I could confirm recently in the context of my
review of Philip Zimbardo's acclaimed book The Lucifer Effect: How Good People turn
Evil, on the social psychology of evil. But against the background of the
book reviewed here I must conclude that the research I am considering here gets
its impetus, especially its funds, from marketing concerns. The framing of the
question in this project recalls many of the problems regarding the
motivational "imaginary" for the increasing use of computer
technology by an increasing number of children and adults. It certainly aims at
profits but mostly at increasing speeds and power with no reference to
economics, politics, and ethics. And all based on a problematic psychology or
vague phenomenology. It does not help that the project
leader announces that he bases his
own thinking on Albert Borgmann's notion of the device paradigm and Don Ihde's notion of the inherent non-neutrality of technology. Regarding
Don Ihde I had already to express my comments in a research draft in 2004. And does not help that Borgmann
claims that "if we
are to challenge the rule of technology, we can only do so through the practice
of engagement" or "to respond through an enduring commitment"
(in Technology
and the Character of Contemporary Life, p. 207, 210) if "we" do not know
what we should be engaged in or committed to, and are able to do so. And it
does not help to read learned third-hand interpretations of Heidegger ang
Borgmann as by Hubert L. Dreyfus on their "How to affirm technology". Such utterances may be psychologically
understood as analog to the Bible's "to speak in tongues" or
"ecstatic utterances" but then under the necessity to "distinguish
true spirits from false" (Mat 24:24, 1
Cor. 13:1, 14:26, 12:10), since we are summoned: "do not believe every spirit, but test
the spirits to see whether they are from God, because many false prophets have
gone out into the world" (1 John 4:1; New American Standard Bible ASB). All this is consistent with a draft of mine
of a critical review of latest tendencies in informatic theorizing
about "design" as contrasted to systems thinking, and related to
postromantic and postmodern tendencies suggested by pre-Socratic sophistry and
post-Kantian aestheticizing (on the basis of the Third Critique, of
"Judgment", and philosophies of Fichte, Schelling, Nietzsche,
Bergson, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, Lyotard). Both Borgmann and Idhe are close to the
tradition represented in the book that is reviewed here and incur into the same
problems.
My explanation for the apparent success of this tradition in certain academic circles is based on the earlier mentioned Lwith's statement that Heidegger's philosophy is in its very essence a theology without God. People with intellectual or, rather, academic ambitions live in circles which, contrary to Isaac Newton and many other scientific luminaries like Werner Heisenberg and others, as well as contrary to university traditions, do not admit theology. They may therefore look for the psychological consolation of abreacting like I myself did with my writing an essay on Belief and Reason, or ultimately by attempting to benefit from the intellectual prestige of endorsing a theology without God. It is not for nothing that a seriously committed man like Francisco Varela looked for a Buddhistic ethics in his A Know-How for Ethics, (my translation of the Italian title), which today in the West is reduced to inconsequential goodwilled or feelgood imperatives. And it is remarkable to note that this attitude to research and ethics is consistent with its banalization in postmodern trends, if yet not so extreme as cyberpunk. This attitude programmatically declares its purpose to shift the focus of product development from the pure functionality and efficiency valued in working places to the needs and desires of its users in everyday life. But the reader may think that if functionality and efficiency aim at needs, it is probable that changed focus shifts towards "desires", which are most emphasized in "everyday life" outside the working sphere. All this is further consistent with ongoing trends that go from the old, classical, serious, absurd Technocracy and the American Dream, towards what has been categorized as techno-progressivism, postcyberpunk, steampunk, and others that are linked from "viridian design", linked in turn from ludic playfulness, while ludic researchers certainly prefer to be seen as applying a (postmodern version of a paradoxically serious) philosophy of play. It is also consistent with the idea of "the sibling society", adults playing or remaining children while children possibly play adults, often in addictive behavior with "silly games", that I have had reasons to ponder on in my blog. As such, it is only an additional, late illustrative example of the object of the book's criticism, particularly illustrative because it represents university-based research.
There are, however, very deep-going
and legitimate strivings embedded in the the above research project, similar to
those in the book that was reviewed here. They may be seen as represented more
clearly by a PhD dissertation by Kei Hoshi on a trend in human-computer
interaction, with the title Here
and now: Foundations and practice of human-experiential design (available
in electronic pdf-format). This research builds mainly upon
some of the American exponents of the "embodied mind" and
"philosophy in the flesh" that I named above, Mark Johnson and George
Lakoff, related to, but not referenced in our reviewed book. The dissertation
refers further to a couple of quite famous books by the American anthropologist
and cross-cultural researcher Edward T. Hall.
When browsing my copy of his The
Silent Language (1959) that I
bought and read in March 1970 together with his The
Hidden Dimension (1966) I realize
how attractive that work is, especially to me, probably because of my own
multi-cultural background. Hall explicitly relates his work to the adapted
psychoanalytical framework by Harry
Stack Sullivan that is at strong
variance from both the earlier mentioned Jung and Cassirer, while the
dissertation's has an occasional reference to "symbolic forms" (p.
44.) Symptomatically, despite one focus on "successful aging in a networked
society" the dissertation ignores literature that can counters its basic
hypotheses, like, say, Sherry Turkle's Alone
Together. It also ignores,
in its evaluations (as on p. 144), the Hawthorne
Effect or
Novelty
Effect that may be especially likely to take
place when dealing with rehabilitation and support of disadvantaged children,
elderly, and others with "special needs" on whom the whole
dissertation is focused.
The dissertation raises the reader's sympathy
because it repeatedly addresses the difficulties of the disabled, elderly
people and children (pp. 48, 106, 123, 130, 133-5, 129-140, 171, 175, 199)
whom, however, the subject of the dissertation is not limited to. The
conclusions are disconcerting in their embedded disclaimer, that the approach
"does promise the possibility of the scientific design of everyday
life" (p. 167.) Promise
the possibility? This promise of (or) possibility is combined with
the claim that design has to ensure that humans can "fulfill
themselves" in the world of things or technology (p. 26), "improving
a mature consciousness of higher aesthetic and cultural life" (p. 39) by
means of design resources like "feelings, aesthetic sensibilities, moral
practice, and spiritual awareness" (p. 40) or, more generally "art,
music and poetry" (p. 49.) Recurring words that recall engagement-motivation as in the
project surveyed in the
previous section above are: pleasurable, enjoyable, enjoyment, immersive,
involvement, harmony, fun, aesthetic experience, natural flow of action,
pleasant, invigorating, and such (pp. 85, 108, 110, 141, 151-3,
156-8, 161-2, 173, 176), i.e. qualities that happen to be often appreciated
even in (addiction to) computer games
as already observed in the above
review of chapter IV of our book.
In the afterword (p. 175 ff.) the dissertation finally starts to resemble more
significantly to our reviewed book in that its author expresses what "it
maybe a romantic and nostalgic idea to imagine that designing for the essential
true nature of our aesthetic life" can survive commercial globalism. The
author does not specify the meaning of "romantic"
(but see e.g. its use in the context of political correctness)
while he repeatedly regrets the speed
of consumption and production in our reckless
industrial era when we get conscientized when something goes wrong. He starts
using the imperatives that
we noticed in our book review, in that we "should no longer tolerate"
and that we "should slow down", etc. Surprisingly, however (in view
of what was adduced above
about the Cartesian mathematizing nature of the computer), he concludes that
the solution according to the message of the dissertation is that
"tangible interaction, unconsciously executed" through the computer
itself will restore "the primacy of action and re-integrates the mind and
the body". He states that here should be no conscious effort in the
behaviors, because experience has already made possible the series of right
actions, but unconsciously, in that it uses the memory that our bodies know,
erasing the awareness of people as "users" but not as humans, and the
need of willpower to act. "To be pleasant and invigorating, life should be
free of the need to always be conscious of the environment in which we
exist."
Please compare these latest conceptions with what the earlier mentioned Richard
Stivers writes in his Technology
as Magic (p. 67) about television programs, different as they are
from computer programs: "The subjectivization (sterilization) of symbols
and their objectification in visual images effectively reduces meaning to
instinctual power. Visual images hit us at an emotional level. When visual
images are subordinate to language and symbolic meaning, as in traditional art,
then the emotions unleashed are integrated by normative reason and made
meaningful. When, on the other hand, visual images become autonomous, reified
symbols, they leave the emotions under the control of the instincts: survival,
aggression, sexuality, and so forth. For the individual (a spectacular reality
creates a radical individualism) reality is emotional and meaning is
instinctual. The implications are astounding. Technology is first and foremost
an efficient or powerful means of acting, visual images are images of power and
possessions, and the 'meaning' of autonomous visual images is instinctual
power. The circle is now complete: a reality of power, a reality without
meaning. - Even when one allows for the discourse accompanying the visual
images of television and the movies to provide meaning for the action, the primary
mode of human interaction is domination/submission."
These quotations should be enough for giving
the reader a taste of where a philosophy and mind in the flesh can carry such
kind of research. The dissertation has clear difficulties in structuring its
eclectic cluster of terms, especially psychological ones, taken from many
different sources, which evolves in the text through a maze of apparent
synonyms that ultimately appeals to the readers' obscure intuition. And this is
done while ignoring economic realities that motivate the financing of such
research in the hope of increasing the profitability or at least cutting costs
in the care of disabled, elderly, and children. Therefore the reader may
suspect the rightness of Sherry Turkle's Alone
Together instead of the dissertation's envisaged harmonious
blending of realities (virtual and whatever). For instance, human experiential
design may end in pleasurable, enjoyable, immersive involvement and
invigorating natural flow of action with a sort of "true companions",
i.e. better experientially designed products with better blended reality than
their forerunners "real dolls".
The dissertation's final appeal to the "unconscious" that earlier in
the the text is merged with the term "presence", and to the
relinquishing of human will (p. 176) is a serious matter. A glance at Edward
Hall's The Silent Language
indicates that the dissertation's reference to presence, along with claims that
most humans are largely
living in a state of unconsciousness, in an "unconscious cultural
grip" (p. 172), also is a dangerous claim. The statement that humans are becomes positivistically
equivalent to that they should
be. See the earlier
reference to Maffesoli on description vs. prescription.
The claim appears to be the more dangerous
when Hall reminds us (p. 65, chap. 4 of my Fawcett 1959 ed.) that the term awareness or rather presence and immersion most used in
the dissertation seems to portray Sullivan's and others' translation of the
psychoanalytical unconscious into social psychology and neurology, which
explains the neglect of the deep psychological and the religious-theological
dimensions. And the bipolarity (the dissertation's dichotomy) between
subjective and objective that the dissertation purports to dissolve by means of
experiential design is envisaged by Hall (p. 126, chap. 8) as being composed of
a triad (formal, informal, and
technical, not considered in the dissertation) to be synthesized by
means of the congruence in art (corresponding to the dissertation's
experiential design.) This should be compared with Carl Jung's conception of
the process of individuation
where the "self" instead of(as in the dissertation, undefined, p.
173) disappearing, indeed appears. In an analog way, the dissertation's
paradoxical ideal of a "blended reality space" (p. 64) characterized
by a "natural flow of action" (p. 157) and recalling other trends
like "digital
materiality" (cf. Google
search) would escape the risk of being confounded with quasi-psychotic
phenomena, up to the extreme of addiction
to computer games. It should be compared with the approach of the ideal to the
real and evaluation of simulation in the dialectic pragmatist
"sweeping-in" process of West Churchman's Singerian
Inquiring Systems. This
conception, eventually incorporated into The Design of Inquiring Systems
(abbreviated here as DIS, published in 1971), both explains the blending of the
real and ideal (DIS pp. 178, 199, 201, 204) under the aegis of progress (cf. individuation), and
the dissertation's insistence (pp. 45, 58, 176) on the merging of the terms
customers, users, persons and humans, corresponding to DIS' (p. 201, 204) ideal of a unified decision maker, client, and
designer.
A further discussion of the dissertation in its relation to the
"flesh" would take us too far but I intend to review it in more
detail elsewhere, including the insight that much talk about motivation,
engagement, natural flow of action, less self-consciousness, and the like
corresponds to classic insights into the meaning of habitude, as exposed by
French philosophers Félix
Ravaisson in his Of Habit
(1838). Well, he did influence
both the earlier mentioned Merleau-Ponty and Janicaud but the path to the late
phenomenology of flesh is tortuous indeed, as indicated, for instance in Jacques
Derrida's book On
Touching: much ethical
content has been corrupted on the way from the sources of phenomenology such as
in Johann Georg
Hamann. On the basis of a salutary sharp
discussion of fundamental philosophical and psychological terms, Ravaisson
cleans up the present terminological mess and concludes, as summarized in the Wikipedia
overview (cf. part II, chap. IV of Of Habit, pp. 97ff. in my French
original De l'Habitude, ed.
by Payot et Rivages, 1997): "The act of consciousness, according to him,
is the basis of all knowledge. Acts of consciousness are manifestations of
will, which is the motive and creative power of the intellectual life. The idea
of God is a cumulative intuition given by all the various faculties of the
mind, in its observation of harmony in nature and in man."
It sound more like a Christian interpretation
of Carl Jung's individuation process. No further comments seem to be necessary
regarding the differences exposed here about the place of consciousness and
will, and consequently of ethics. In the spirit of Heidegger (cf. above)
ethics tends to vanish as in the most challenging phenomenological approaches
to information science that started as early as with Hubert Dreyfus'
struggle with What
Computers Can't Do: The Limits to Artificial Intelligence
(1979) and William
Barrett's Death of
the Soul: From Descartes to the Computer
(1987). It would be naive to believe that later advances of computer and
communication technology could have automatically bootstrapped these
technologies from their own Cartesian grounds, making these works obsolete. It
recalls the technological belief, countered in our reviewed book and much
philosophy of technology, that the problems of technology can and must be
solved by means of more technology, that is, more is tautologically better
because of presumed progress.
The question arises of whether the supposedly integrative function of the
"bodily flesh" is a tacit, creative revival of the "myth"
or (in terms of this book review) of the "technological imaginary" of
artificial
intelligence that now is being
turned into a computer-supported artificially embodied intelligence. All this
while the soul indeed dies together with ethics and religion, in the illusion
that it all will be synthesized
and replaced
by art or some of its aberrations in
computer games.