UME UNIVERSITY
Institute of
Information Processing Š ADB
Postal
address: S-901 87
UME (Sweden) |
Tel
(direct dialing): +46 90
166030 |
Telefax: +46 90
166126(166688) |
Email
(Internet): kivanov@cs.umu.se |
Professor
KRISTO IVANOV
Chairman,
Administrative Data Processing
Draft 24 February 1992
The
founding father of mathematical logic, Leibniz, is known for having once
made the significant remark that music was "a hidden pactice of the soul,
which does not know that it is dealing with number....In a confused and
unnoticed kind of perception the soul achieves that which, in the midst of
clearer perceptions, it is not able to observe. It therefore the soul does not
notice that it calculates, it yet senses the effect of its unconscious
reckoning, be this as joy over harmony or as oppression over discord."
(von Franz, 1970, pp. 32-33, quoting from a letter from Leibniz to Goldbach,
April 12, 1712, as referred by Ernest Bindel, Die giptischen Pyramiden,
Stuttgart, 1966, pp. 26f. See also Bindels Die Zahlengrundlagen der Musik,
Stuttgart, 1950.)
This
reminds us of the fact that music has been recognized as being intimately
related to mathematics, something which has been also remarked by
psychologists and many of us in daily observations about connections
of skills in people around us. In Greek mythology Apollo or the god patronizing
music is appears often to be also the god of clear thinking, of medicine, etc. (Groves,
1960). The Pythagorean school discovered the mathematical basis of the musical
concords, e.g. that what the ear accepts as the same note an octave higher
is produced by a string exactly half as long. Morality could be seen as a mean
between opposites, a proper "tuning" or harmony of the souls.
Mathematical relations were already being discovered in the physical
universe an Pythagoreans thought that they could find a mathematical basis for
religion and morality. "Mousike", which included poetry and dance,
played a great part in Greek education . Harmonics was considered an exact
science together with arithmetic, geometry, and astronomy, where harmonics was
considered as the applied aspect of number (Kitto, 1957, pp. 192-193;
Kline, 1954, pp. 97, 116). Plato has been referred to believe that he who
steers the music of a people steers also its politics.
Later
in the history of music we hear for istance about Frank of Kln, or of Paris, a
German theorician of music who about 1260 wrote the Ars Cantus Mensurabilis,
and the Compendium Discantus, where principles were set forth for defining the
precise value relations among musical notes and for developing a
theory of intervals. Through Giuseppe Zerlino (1517-1590), as well as through
influences passing from John Dunstable to others, Frank of Kln's mathematical
view of music was developed into an "applied mathematics" concerning
the system of the universe as it was reflected in the world of music
[Enciclopedia della musica [La nuova], 1983 #11, p. 285].
All
this indicates one possible background of the religious aspects of today's
"worship" of so called artificial intelligence, but also of the
serious efforts of some modern mathematicians who approach the great
problems of our time through a study of the history of mathematics (Zellini,
1985a; Zellini, 1985b; Zellini, 1988).
In
considering the religious and ethical aspects of music as mathematics
there are, however, ambiguous tendencies. They may throw some light on why, for
instance, in the area of computer science a whole book has been dedicated
to the formal aspects of computer science (Hofstadter, 1979) without any
attention being paid to the concept of God or to divine inspiration, as it
can be inferred from the index of the book. Of ten index references to the
word God and eight references to the acronym GOD not a single one refers to a
serious treatment of God or of theological subjects. Entries such as religion,
divine, morality or ethics do not appear at all in the index. The whole
discourse is held on a playful level and the nature of this playfulness could
be a fruitful object of research itself.
Masters
as Bach and Schoenberg constructed and advocated vast mathematical theories for
the composition of music, but is has sometimes been believed that "In such
theories cold reason rather than an innefable, spiritual feeling supplies the
creative pattern"; at the same time, however, "Essentially both
mathematician and composer are moved by a divine afflatus that enables
them to 'see' and 'know' the final edifice before one stone is laid" (Kline,
1954, p.342, 511).
The
apparent ambiguity about the place of reason verus of divine afflatus
as apparent in music may be removed if they are seen as an expression of
the historical opposition between sacred versus profane natural law. John Locke
is quoted for having said that the Scriptures confirm the moral laws which
reason discovers and Immanuel Kant, among others, for having believed that our
morals are the basis for religion rather than the other way around (Kline,
1954, p.309). This may be also the background for the unclear relation
between religion and morality or ethics in the work of the rare scientists who
have cared to introduce these concerns in systems science (Churchman,
1979). In any case it would explain how the divine afflatus mentioned above is
implicitly understood as deriving from reason. One significant danger,
obviously, that all this leads to identify reason with mathematics and to
becoming "too mathematical and not sufficiently scientific" (Kline,
1954, p.382).
This
train of thoughts evidences how a study of musical aspects of our problem
situation may suggest interesting research. An important hypothesis is
that the danger of becoming too mathematical and not sufficiently
scientific is what characterizes the increasing application of the computer
seen as an embodyment of mathematics. Other more hypotheses may be
suggested by a study of debates in the history of music.
One
general hypothesis based on the intimate realtionship between music and
mathematics is that the study of historical debates in the field of music
may originate insights in debates that are going on, or should be going on in
the computer and information science seen as applied mathematics. In this
context we are reminded of the conflicts between Claudio Monteverdi and
Giovanni Maria Artusi about offences against the rules of composition. Perhaps
that was related to Giovanni Paolo Colonna's (1637-1695) famous criticism of
Arcangelo Corelli's (1653-1713) passage in his third sonata in op.2.
Then
we have also the conflict between Christoph Willibald Gluck and Johann
Sebastian Bach concerning ethics versus aesthetics of inessential
musical ornament in relation to "truth to nature" according to the
ideals of Jean Jacques Rousseau and the philosophers of Diderot's
Encyclopaedia. Gluck (1714-1787) being influenced by rationalism and naturalism
refused the hedonistic "playful" principle in music which would
regard that form of art as entertainement for the senses. Gluck's reform
of melodrama, beyond its deep purely musical meaning, is considered to reflect
a rebellion of ethical character.
One
of the most famous debates is that between Richard Wagner and Nietzsche (Nietzsche,
1983) concerning matters related to sociology, politics, history,
psychology, and moral philosophy, in terms of which e.g. Der Ring des
Nibelungen can be interpreted. In that context, among the issues which are
debated, figure the role of Christianity versus nazism, communism and
"dialectical negations", morals, etc. including their relation
to Schopenhauer's aesthetics were, with reference to Kant, music is considered
as the direct expression of "the thing in itself". Reflection on
music is one fundamental theme of Nietzsche's philosophical thought. Having
formulated the way to today's relativism, nihilism, and postmodernism,
he considered music as a stimulus for penetrating the essence of Western
thought and for criticizing its schemes and structures [Dictionary of
composers, 1981 #984; Enciclopedia della musica [La nuova], 1983 #11;
Nietzsche, 1983 #1113]. This is clearly a task that is analog to the one we
have defined for our research program in the context of the use of the
"mathematicized" information technology.
Coming
closer to our times and later debates about so called modern music one must
certainly note Arnold Schnberg's suspension of tonality and his
development of a new "method of composition with twelve tones related
only to one another" gave his works a basis of organization that enabled
him to write in larger instrumental forms, but these innovations were
attacked for making music unintelligible or "mathematical". (Dictionary
of composers, 1981).
One
thing that could be learnt in the context of musical debates and conflicts is
that, in spite of they being often interpreted in terms of curious purely
personal antagonisms or questions of pure "taste" (a term that has
deserved serious reflection in the history and theory of art), they still may
the visible expression of important objective matters. To ignore them may
open the way to what we today call ethical relativism or situational ethics.
These people obviously struggled for certain ideals and sometimes dedicated
their lives to certain causes. Their conflicts may have been as much serious
as, and perhaps even related to, say, the conflicts in the world of mathematics
between Georg Cantor, Leopold Kronecker, David Hilbert and Jan Brouwer (Reid,
1970, pp. 26, 50, 99, 148ff,173). To ignore them for the sake of a not well
understood "success" or "power" of later mathematics
may have led to consequences that are becoming full visible with the
widespread use of the applied mathematics of computers, and only now begin to
get formulated (Barrett, 1987; Davis & Hersh, 1986).
The
meaning of debates is being misunderstood from the scientific
methodological point of view whenever one thinks that the fact that a Beethoven
or Monteverdi were opposed in their time, and yet are recognized today,
shows that opposition is a dubious attitude of mind. The methodological
catch is that there are no "control groups" to validate such a coarse
inference. Some oppositions may have been good, other bad, and this is not
known a priori. We do not really know what would have happened if no opposition
had existed. As a matter of fact we do not even know what has happened today
and, if we do not believe to some kind of social darwinism, we cannot
infer that things have turned out to be good only because they have succeeded
in the struggle for survival and today happen to be considered successful. If
this or that composer had not been opposed he might not have evolved as he did,
or one hundred other bad composers with deleterious influences would perhaps
have made their way, etc.
It
is indeed remarkable how the superficial interpretation of debate, conflict and
opposition has become popular today in the light of the story about the
accumulation of knowledge. If somebody shows to be apprehensive for
the consequences of computerization he may be rebutted with the
observation that people in earlier generations have been also apprenhensive
about railways, telephones, etc., with the implicit message that if one
apprenhension turned out to be misplaced, the other will too. The reasoning
may be extended to the critique of the attitudes of youngsters, and so on. Our
proposed reserach, then can also be seen as an attempt to reinstate the
importance of not only history but also of the concept of debate, dialogue or
conversation as a source of knowledge.even in the exact sciences, in a
rhetorical and dialectical tradition.
In
summary we claim that some particular understanding of the computer phenomenon
and of the implications of the formalization of society in terms of
increased utilization of computers may be obtained through the study of music,
especially in its relations to mathematics. Attempts have already been made to
study organizations through music (Ziegenfuss, 1989). Experiences of
education for creativity also point to the importance of certain kinds of music
for stimulating images and emotions and for reintegration of aesthetics
and ethical sensibility into science (Hill, 1989). The implications are that
analog efforts could and should be made for the purpose of developing
better methods of systems design and for better utilization of computer
support.
Barrett, W. (1987). Death of
the soul: From Descartes to the computer. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Churchman, C. W. (1979). The
systems approach and its enemies. New York: Basic Books.
Davis, P. J., & Hersh, R.
(1986). Descartes' dream: The world according to mathematics. New York
and London: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, and Penguin Books.
Dictionary of composers (1981). .
Papermac - Macmillan:
Enciclopedia
della musica [La nuova] (1983). . Milano: Garzanti.
Groves, R. (1960). The Greek
myths (2 vols.).
Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books.
Hill, R. C. (1989). Freeing the
internal environment for problem-solving and creativity: A precursor to
education and the future. In Proc. of the ISSS Int. Society for the Systems
Sciences, 33rd Annual Conference, Edinburgh, Scotland, 2-7 July 1989. Vol. 1
(pp. 152-158).
Hofstadter, D. (1979). Gdel,
Escher, Bach: An eternal golden braid. A metaphorical fugue on minds and
machines in the spirit of Lewis Carroll. New York: Basic Books.
Kitto, H. D. F. (1957). The
Greeks (2nd ed.). London: Penguin Books.
Kline, M. (1954). Mathematics
in Western Culture. London: Allen & Unwin.
Nietzsche, F. (1983). Il caso
Nietzsche contra Wagner [The case Nietzsche versus Wagner]. Milano:
Unicopli.
Reid, C. (1970). Hilbert.
New York: Springer Verlag.
von Franz, M. L. (1970). Number
and time: Reflections leading towards a unification of depth psychology and
physics. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Zellini, P. (1985a). Breve
storia dell'infinito (2nd ed.). Milano: Adelphi.
Zellini, P. (1985b). La
ribellione del numero. Milano: Adelphi.
Zellini, P. (1988). Humanistic
and ethical aspects of mathematics No. Report UMADP-RRIPCS-4.88). Ume
University, Inst. of Information Processing.
Ziegenfuss, J. T., Jr. (1989).
Exploring organizations through music: Commonalities between human and natural
systems. In Proc. of the ISSS Int. Society for the Systems Sciences, 33rd
Annual Conference, Edinburgh, Scotland, 2-7 July 1989. Vol. 3 (pp.
215-223).