UMEÅ UNIVERSITY
Dept. of Informatics
Kristo Ivanov, kivanov@informatik.umu.se
(version 020507-1630)
Documentation for research seminars starting October 10th
and November 14th 2001
http://www.informatik.umu.se/seminarier/2001/1002717000-1002718800.mit-huset.mc413
http://www.informatik.umu.se/seminarier/2001/1005740100-1005746400.mit-huset.mc413
ETHICS AND POLITICS IN DESIGN AND SYSTEM CULTURES
1. INTRODUCTION AND PRESENTATION:
2. SUBJECT-TITLE "Creating a Design Culture"
3. PAGES 39, 41, 122, 147, 156, 167, 193, 204
4. PAGE 61
5. PAGES 90-91
6. PAGE 95
7. PAGES 96-98
8. PAGE 101
9. PAGE 104
10. PAGE 117
11. PAGE 123, 126, 159-160 [cf. Aristotle below]
12. PAGES 132-135
13. PAGE 153
14. PAGES 156-158
15. PAGES 171-172
16. PAGES 173-174
17. PAGE 180-181
18. PAGES 183, 197-198
19. PAGES 185-187
20. PAGES 189-190
21. PAGE 204
22. PAGE 207
23. From Matti, G. (2000). Det intuitiva livet: Hans
Larssons vision om enhet i en splittrad tid. Uppsala: Gidlunds Förlag.
Summary in English. Pages 243-245:
24. From Matti, G. (2000). Det intuitiva livet: Hans
Larssons vision om enhet i en splittrad tid. Uppsala: Gidlunds Förlag.
In Swedish:
25. From Heidegger, M. (1968). What is called thinking?
New York: Harper & Row. (Trans. by J. Glenn Gray. Orig. Was Heisst Denken?
Tübingen: Max Niemeyer, 1954):
26. From Plato. (1961). Plato: The collected dialogues.
Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press - Böllingen. (ed. from Epis. VII 343c-344c):
27. From Aristotle. (1984). The complete work of Aristotle:
The revised Oxford translation (2 Volumes). Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press.
(Ed. by Jonathan Barnes. ISBN 0-691-09950-2.) Vol 2: Nicomachean Ethics:
28. From Pierre Aubenque's book "La prudence chez Aristote:
avec un appendice sur la prudence chez Kant" [Phronesis according to Aristotle:
with an appendix on phronesis according to Kant], Quadrige/PUF, 1993 (1961).
Ref. also to the documentation of Kristo Ivanov' seminar 15 October 1997 at
Umeå university's dept. of informatics, his free edited translation,
and to Kristo's essay (www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/chinese.html)."Strategy
and design for information technology":
29. From Kant, I. (1790/1987). Critique of judgement.
Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett. (Trans. with an introduction by Werner S.
Pluhar. Foreword by Mary J. Gregor.):
30. From Norris, C. What's wrong with postmodernism:
Critical theory and the ends of philosophy . New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf,
1990:
31. From Ferry, L. Homo aestheticus : The invention of
taste in the democratic age, trans. by Robert de Loaiza. Chicago: The University
of Chicago Press, 1993:
32. Example (in Swedish) of neglected type social-political
and ethical analysis, in one main Swedish theoretical approach to design:
Paulsson, G., & Paulsson, N. (1956). Tingens bruk och prägel [Things
for everyday use and life form]. Stockholm: Kooperativa Förbundets Bokförlag,
chap on Nyttoting och livsform. Pages 115-123:
33. From Fides et Ratio. Encyclical letter . Rome, 1998:
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_15101998_fides-et-ratio_en.html
§§85-87, 97-98 also in http://www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/PerspSem2000.html:
34. From. Veritatis Splendor. Encyclical letter . Rome,
1993: http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_06081993_veritatis-splendor_en.html,
also in also http://www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/PerspSem2000.html:
35. CONCLUDING REFLECTION:
This seminar, and a possible follow-up seminar later on, takes
advantage of the opportunity afforded by Erik Stolterman's request for comments
to his and Harold Nelson's manuscript of a book on
"Creating a design culture"
(draft version ofJuly 2001:v2), in order to highlight some political ethical
problems that are implicit in certain design-conceptions.
A background and basis for my comments and problematizations
will be my own papers on some cores ideas of later years' emphasis on design,
that I recently summarized in
(reprints available in the stands in front of our lunch
room)
on the basis of the following earlier partial essays
http://www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/page6.html
http://www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/chinese.html
http://www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/PerspSem2000.html
(especially items 6.12 and 7, but also 5.7, 6.2, 6.4, 6.9, 6.12, and 8.4.13 on
eclecticism).
Selected pieces of text from the manuscript will be related to
dialectical systems theory as exemplified in
http://www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/chuindex.html
or
http://www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/chuindex.pdf
by the keywords "design-designer", "change",
"teleology-purposes", "implementation", "action", "ethics", "guarantor",
"politics-power", "romanticism", and "aesthetics", in my extended word-index to
West Churchman's book "The design of inquiring system".
The participants to the seminar, especially those who are
following the ongoing course on "Creating a design culture" which is based on
the manuscript are encouraged to complete its reading prior to the seminar. It
is recommended that everyone has the manuscript available during the seminar:
see Erik's invitation to furnish copies, in his collective e-mail the the
department's alias on September 6th. The seminar will he held preferably without
overheads but, rather, with verbal references and readings from selected pages
of the manuscript which, then, are necessary for following the argument. Please
note the authors's wish that the draft not be quoted outside our
department.
1. INTRODUCTION AND PRESENTATION:
- Despite decreasing dialogue with increasing department. Cf. also the
concept of "university", and the example of being able to dialogue with even
other local departments and disciplines, dept. of religious studies, seminar 9
Oct 2001 on "radical orthodoxy" and "cultural hermeneutics/cultural critique" or
how do we interpret cultures, and the relationship betweent the interpretation,
production and transformation of cultures
-
- Own attempts to system and
democratic participation: dialectic service to each other instead of only
seeking external alliances. Cf. design of "whole"
-
- Not expected that this is others' responsibility: but motivated by the
risk of students' "overload" that inhibits their possible critical attitude,
and by tendencies to redefine informatics as a "design discipline"
-
- Design Culture as
skillful self-contained "whole" and reminder of foreign neglected fragments of
neo-romantic and neo-mystical thought (cf. Bergson, in Garzanti Enciclopedia di
Filosofia and Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
.
BUT: -
-
- Examples?
- International? (Dubuisson-Hennion,
Maldonado, Buchanan, Coyne)
- Philosophical?
(Kant->Fichte&Schelling, & Bergson&Larsson neoromanticism &
neomysticism of Nietzsche-Heidegger & Merleau Ponty, vs. indirect Aristotle
& Kant through Nussbaum-Dunne & Makkreel, Jung through Hillman vs. J.J.
Clarke 1992). Cf. Ehn's Marx+Wittgenstein+Heidegger or Dahlbom's Weber+Latour
vs. modernity
- Historical (Fidias, Vitruvius, Vinci, Morris & Ruskin,
Bauhaus, etc.)?
-
- Eclecticism (vs. pragmatism), and therefore: Ethical?
(Why necessary, or useful, or good, if not "true-right")
-
- What follows:
Page numbers with edited excerpts related to design ethics and politics, out of
the manuscript Creating a Design Culture, or other specified works. Connections
with dialectical systems approach will be drawn during the seminar (references
in seminar call, above)
2. SUBJECT-TITLE "Creating a Design Culture"
- Does it matter? (Essence & being)
-
- Create=Design? Does it
matter what is designed, another design, a process vs object, a culture, or a
system?
-
- What is design? A compound form of inquiry composed of the
true, the ideal and the real (p.27). It is basically "caused" by a service
relationship (35). Design is understood to be primarily about making something
concrete, or planning for something, or making something aesthetically pleasing,
but there is much more to design today: one of the key distinction is that
design decisions are made as design judgments made within the context of the
adequate rather than the comprehensive, leading to the creation of something
which has not existed before (88). Design is not only about creating something
new: it is about creating a whole by adding something new to something already
in existence (107). Design is about creating aspects of the real word (112).
Design needs to be understood as a whole process that extends through the entire
time that design is in use [life cycle?]; sometimes is goes even beyond that,
and the concept of evolving design as a never-ending design process is growing
in popularity (156). Design is paradoxical: it is not-attachments and total
engagement, flux and permanence, knowing and naiveté, experience and
fresh eyes, collaboration and solitude, process and structure, cyclic and
episodic, control and uncontrollable, unique and universal, infinite and finite,
timeless and temporal, splendor and evil (175). [And form and
content?]
-
- What is (ought to be?) a culture? Cf. Webster's, The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Dictionary of the History of Ideas. Cf. environment
vs. context. The question of cultural relativism and innovation vs. tradition
(cf. reference to the tradition of design in the context of creating a design
culture)
3. PAGES 39, 41, 122, 147, 156, 167, 193, 204
- The core relationship in the design process is designer-client
-
- In
a service relationship the designer is responsible to more than the client
assuming accountability for others who will be affected, including stakeholders,
stockholders, decision makers, producers or makers, end users, customers,
surrogate clients, future generations and natural environment
-
- Common
meaning among designers, clients, decision makers, stakeholders, surrogate
clients, and others with logical or moral connections
-
- Design dialogue
and diathenic graphologue is done through an iterative process including clients
and other stakeholders
-
- Evolving design changes the basic relationships
between the designer, clients, and end users
-
- A designer can always
argue that he or she is only trying to make someone else satisfied. It can be a
client, customer, stakeholder, or a user
-
- There is symmetry between the
carefulness needed from the designer and the user
-
- To be a good designer
also means to be a good leader
4. PAGE 61
- A real world event projected onto three different frames-of-reference can
reveal dramatically different understandings, values and meaning, yet remains a
coherent singular event in the world. It may be seen as vice from a social point
of view, or as a virtue in the business world, while treated with indifference
in the political arena. Complex ideas or beliefs are perceived as paradoxes when
images from two different frames-of-reference of the same complex thing are
viewed together. Understanding emerges from a unification of difference, a
composition, the shape of something more complexly comprehensive, rather than
from dominance of one image over another or resolution by compromise or
trade-off.
5. PAGES 90-91
- To critique different types of designs from the perspective of wholes, or
to make an evaluation of all kinds of wholes there are three types of frames of
reference (with their respective evaluations attributes): real (adequate,
significant, essential), true (efficient, aesthetic, ethical), and ideal (true,
beautiful, good). Designed wholes are created by intention to evoke emergent
forms and behaviors that embody the essence of that which really counts in
defining and developing human potential more fully.
-
- The adequate can be
understood as being discerned by judgments of composition among "purposeful
differences", like between justice and mercy, or creativity and control.
Compositional judgments do not result in reconciliation, resolution, or
trade-off, but in an adequate composite.
-
- The essential value of each
difference is enhanced and enriched by being brought into a particular
compositional relationship that adequately facilitates the desired end or
outcome of an emergent design. The attribute of a designed whole dealing with
the essential refers to discernment and inclusion of anything that is judged to
be an intentional necessity in fulfilling authentic human needs and desires,
desiderata at both the level of the particular and collective.
-
- The
significant, as an attribute of the designed whole deals with meaning
making.
6. PAGE 95
- We use the concept of desiderata (desires) as an inclusive whole --
including all three approaches: aesthetics, ethics and reason but transcending
their aggregate effect in the form of an emergent quality characteristic of
compositions or wholes, or the world as an integrative outcome of all three
approaches in concert. Is the escape route from the strategies of change which
box us into analysis paralysis (description and explanation of what IS), value
paralysis of blind action (ethics and morality of what OUGHT-TO-BE) or slavish
mimicry.
-
- Cf. pp. 132-135
7. PAGES 96-98
- Needs assessment is assumed to be the necessary first step to a design
activity meant to bring change to a social institution. Focusing on needs,
however, has allowed motivation triggered by what we desire or how we know our
desires to remain undeveloped -- the desiderata. Human intention, when motivated
from desiderata rather than need, reshapes the entire process for intentional
change. Desiderata can be expressed through many domains: the mind's desire, the
heart's desire, and the soul's desire.
-
- Desiderata are not a response to
the problem of an unfilfilled basic human need. The negative impulse towards
action which arises out of such a felt need is completely different from the
positive impulse born out of the desire to create situations, systems of
organization or concrete artifacts which enable our becoming more fully
developed in all our promise as human beings.
-
- As humans we have to use our desires as a way to understand how we can
fulfill our lives. But desires are not all good. When we reflect upon them
and examine them we will find that we have to deal with both good as well
as bad desires. In this process we have to accept both types. We have to discipline
the negative desires and live with the positive. To recognize and differentiate
positive from negative desires is one of our lifelong tasks as humans, the
process of "befriending our desires".
8. PAGE 101
- Intention is not a vision but the aiming and [sic, at?] the emergence of
a desired outcome. Starting in a situation ("ready") desiderata helps to aim,
to form the intention. The outcome is not there when the process begins. The
outcome emerges based on the situation, desiderata and intention. This process
is very different from many common understandings where action is seen as
a consequence of a defined goal. The goal is not there to define action. In
any intentional process we know that we easily can produce many "goal" situations
that would be closer to our desires than the present. But intention is not
only about where to go but also about how to go there. [cf. means-ends]
-
- Within the tradition of Zen a deep understanding of
intention as a process of aiming has been developed, referring to careful
attention, and by letting go of many of our everyday assumptions on how to reach
our goals in the most efficient
way.
9. PAGE 104
- Alignment is composed of appreciation and desiderata that together with the
designer's and client's intentions leads to the "tremendous mystery" of a parti
(a compelling organizing template guiding the designer in the succeeding design
steps), composed of telos (purpose-ends) and soul (image-vision). Alignment is a
synthesis of both group process and team dynamics. The condition of alignment
integrates the intentional behavior of the individual
actors.
10. PAGE 117
- Design communication:
-
- Both solitude and
collaboration
- Nonlinear dynamic process
- Systemic relationships among
individuals engaged in design
- Different roles and skills, perspectives and
authority
- Trust and common intent, common understanding, collective
action
-
- Both intrapersonally and interpersonally
- Dialogue and visual
literacy
- Common understanding, common meaning
- Helping to form shared
understandings
- Conversation , dialogue and diathenic
graphologue
11. PAGE 123, 126, 159-160 [cf. Aristotle below]
- Judgment if a key dimension in the process of design, and the ability to
make good judgments distinguishes good design, making designers valuable to
society, and making designers and leaders one and the same. Judgment is the
heart of wisdom in all its manifestations. Judgment is the means and wisdom is
the outcome. Judgment is knowing based on knowledge that is inseparable from the
knower, generated in the particularity of a situation, and revealed through the
actions of the knower. Skills and competencies, whish are forms of judgment can
be practiced and mastered in support of future actions taken from judgments in
particular situations but should not be confused as knowledge for judgment
itself. There is in judgment knowledge a connection to what has traditionally
been considered wisdom.
-
- The value of judgment is that it allows
indiduals to overcome analysis and value paralysis, and engage with the messy
complexityof life in a way that, when done well, can bring function, beauty, and
meaning to human existence.
-
- In each and every moment of the design
process there are two dimensions that have to be dealt with. (1) The techne
dimension of how to do things right, where the designer needs certains skills to
see logical relationships, especially the relationship between cause and action,
(2) the phronesis dimension about doing the right things, where the designer
needs the ability to make design judgments, requiring preparedness to take
action, a well developed intuition, a perceptive sense of wholeness, and an
ethical and aesthetic appreciation of the design situation. Which dimension to
focus on is a question of balance and symmetry, not of right or wrong or of
dominance or equality. Symmetry is an aesthetic concept and is more in line with
Wittgenstein's sense of "fit" in a
situation.
12. PAGES 132-135
- An appreciative judgment is about something that is preferred because it
is "liked" as a personal preference and "looks" attractive or "feels preferable"
due to a sense of familiarity, comfort or membership in a larger context of
similar actions or things. It is grounded in a sense of certainty that comes
from a strong sense of self-assurance coming from membership or leadership
in a collective which exhibits desirable qualities by consensus.
-
- Navigational
judgments are based on the ends to be found in the moment, survival, to gain
advantage in the moment, including the contribution to a larger social good that
is not predetermined and accessible in the moment.
-
- Framing judgement is
at the heart of the deliberation in determining the adequate. Despite the
anxiety of not having enough information and knowledge, still, as a designer,
you have to act, ignoring
-
- Compositional judgements includes aesthetic,
ethical and rational considerations calling forth a compositional whole which
displays qualities and attributes particular to the unique character of the
ultimate particular that serves the design intention most adequately. The
compositional whole is formed with the aid of the guiding domains of aesthetics,
ethics, and reason but not in the mode of analysis. Unlike the famous example of
blind men describing an elephant there is not yet elephant.
-
- Cf. p.
95
13. PAGE 153
- Compositions can be considered to be efficient, effective, good, just,
frightening, evil, beautiful or sublime. The ultimate evaluation is prophesized
by the designers and verified by the real world. The real value of a composition
is determined by its success in meeting the desires of the client and the
intentions of the designers. Its intrinsic worth is determined even more by the
unexpected presence the design exhibits on its own as it becomes an agent of
influence and change [improvement?] in its own right -- thus recreating its
creators.
14. PAGES 156-158
- The production process is cared for by people with complex and contradictory
demands, needs, wants. There is no way of escaping these tensions and design
thrives on them.
-
- One way to deal with these tensions is
portrayed with the concept of "flow", or the feeling we get when we perform a
task in a way that removes us from conscious deliberation with all uncertainties
and anxieties about doing "the right thing" in "the right way". When in flow we
do not think about what we are doing, we just participate in it. We let go of
our planning and calculating mind, and still are in perfect control but also
free to do whatever we desire, to "feel the
force".
15. PAGES 171-172
- But there is no guarantor of design "out there
-
- There are no givens
in the design process
-
- Restricted only by our present reality and our
imagination
-
-
- We can find a guarantor of design only in the
development of our design character
-
- Designer's judgment must depend
heavily on core values
-
- The designer has to believe in the capacity of
make good judgments
-
- We consider the designer as a self-reflective
individual with a fully developing character
-
-
- How to reduce the
worries about how to make good design decisions that in turn lead to avoidance
of responsibility?
-
- Teach designers how to argue, rigorously and
critically, so that they can call their minds their own - the only way to not be
uncritical moral relativists
16. PAGES 173-174
- To base our design actions and judgments on our own core character we must
constantly examine our practice and our thoughts, to develop our own design
character
-
- To to this self-examination we need intellectual tools, i.e.
concepts and ideas, that can help us analyse ourselves as designers, and a
serious dialogue on design
responsibility
17. PAGE 180-181
- How is it possible to become a [good?] designer and accept design when evil
is intimate to the whole enterprise? A good next step is to accept the nature of
design and prepare accordingly. This includes accepting the uncertain,
contradictory, dangerous and yet promising challenges of design: no right
answers, no givens, service to others, both/and/neither...
-
- The splendor
of design outreaches the grasp of the potential and actual consequences of evil
in design.
18. PAGES 183, 197-198
- It seems as if functionality, efficiency, smartness, usefulness or whatever
measurements we can come up with cannot fully capture the way people relate to a
design. The way a design is valued and judged must instead be understood as a
result of the experience evoked by the design and by an aesthetical judgment of
the whole. It has to do with composition, with balance and relation between all
possible aspects of a design.
-
- This is not about superficial
aestheticism. The meaning and value of a design is a feeling of complexity and
of being moved -- and as a consequence a feeling of being changed. When we face
the soul of a design, our basic assumptions and our worldview are challenged. It
may not be much, but something profound happens to us.
-
- Page 197: The
seminal quality for assurance of excellence in design is the presence of design
character. This is because the different aspects of design contribute to an
understanding of design only when the core values of design reside in the
designer's character...The question is how to develop the core in order to
become a good designer capable of doing good design (two different
challenges).
19. PAGES 185-187
- When we are shown how different parts and components are interrelated, how
structure, form, material, structure, smell, taste, etc. fit the overall theme
and purpose of the thing we are supposed to evaluate, we are learning to see and
appreciate the intrinsic value of the thing itself. Value is defined not
dependent of context of a larger system.
-
- As humans we do not only
evaluate a design based on its intrinsic value. It is more often the opposite.
We often take a much more intentional or purpose oriented approach in the
process of evaluating designs. We want them not only to have value but also to
be meaningful. A thing has meaning when we can see how this thing is connected
to something else that we value.
-
- This may lead to an infinite regress
since we can always ask what is the meaning of each new thing or "level" we
connect to. There are two ways to stop this regress: one is religion with leads
to a "thing" where we are not allowed to ask what meaning is ("what is the
meaning of God?"), and the other what is to connect to something that has
intrinsic value and does not have to have meaning.
-
- This examination of
the intricate relationship of value and meaning shows the difficulty and
complexity of evaluating designs. The relationship also presupposes a static
reality, while our perception of the reality and our knowledge constantly
changes, and thereby changes our preconditions for evaluating the design. The
soul of a design is something emerging when the value and meaning of a design is
in resonance with the particular
situation.
20. PAGES 189-190
- To decide if a composition is successful is difficult. A design with a
strong composition but situated in a context for which it is not designed or in
a context that has radically changed over time, can obstruct change. But if the
design is situated in a suitable context [=what we do not want to change], it
may create stability in the midst of a complext and changing environment [=what
we cannot change]...It is always a matter of the ultimate
particular.
-
- One aspect of ensoulment, sometimes used as a measure of
quality, is timelessness, that a design is not only appreciated at a specific
time and place but also valued over time and by people from different times and
places.
-
- How is this possible if we have defined the soul of a design as the resonance
between is value and meaning in the specific situation? One answer could be
that the soul in a timeless design is not timeless because it resonates with
a specific situation, but, rather, because it resonates with something larger,
something more "eternal".
21. PAGE 204
- A leader is always a designer, since the leader's role is to lead people
into a new reality. This is true even (sic) when a designer acts in service of a
client. The designer still has the obligation to open up new ideas, new
realities, based on the desiderata of the client. And since there is no
guarantor of design except the character of the designer, there is now way to
escape the role of also being a leader.
-
- To be a designer is to take on
the role of all that is expected by a designer. But it is not a passive
acceptance of something predefined. There is no true role for design - there are
no fixed meanings of what constitutes a good designer, with his unique talent,
calling and character.
22. PAGE 207
- The emergence of a design culture implies the recognition of a new form of
democracy, based on designerly relationships of service [cf. administration vs.
politics]. Another implication is that of inclusiveness which embraces
diversity, complexity, and contradiction. The design tradition [vs. culture that
is being created?] is inclusive of other traditions of inquiry and action. In
design there is no "science war" or "war of cultures". Design deals with the
real, which by definition includes all possible aspects of reality.
-
- The
[design] competence to create the world that people experience and that becomes
the very fabric of what they believe to be reality is beyond full
cmprehension.
23. From Matti, G. (2000). Det intuitiva livet: Hans Larssons vision om enhet i
en splittrad tid. Uppsala: Gidlunds Förlag. Summary in English. Pages
243-245:
- This study deals with the Swedish philosopher Hans Larsson (1862-1944) who
was also known as a writer, educator and cultural figure. The study shows how
Larsson's doctrine of intuition manifested an alternative understanding of
rationality in relation to the dominant view of the period. His debut as an
author, Intuition (1892), constituted a critique of the age which, in
polemics with the positivist and naturalist viewpoints, argued for a
rehabilitation of the importance of feeling and intuition in art, science and
philosophy.
-
- Larsson understood intuition as a synthesis of a
multiplicity of representations into an apprenhension of the whole. At the time,
Intuition was generally seen as an expression of the neo-romantic spirit of the
age. There was an existential dimension to his description of how intuition
leads to self-understanding as well as a better understanding of the reality
around us, that is, to self-realization.
-
- Larsson described the process
of moving from disunity and divisions to unity and wholeness. This description
is said to hold for all dimensions and levels, that is, for the individual, the
collective and for the culture as a whole. This process leads to spiritual
health and it constitutes an ideal for art, science, pedagogics and everyday
life. "Intuitive culture" is the image of the ideal society.
-
- His view
of rationality was rather special. The intuitive manner of proceeding, in his
view, is often an apparently illogical procedure which in actuality manifests
the highest form of "logic" or rationality, that is, the organic intuitive
"precise logic". It was contrasted with the positivist "coarse logic" of, and
overconfidence in analytic discursive thinking with its blind faith in natural
science. The new century, however, brought with it anti-intellectual and
irrationalist cultural currents, as tendecies in Henri Bergson's philosophy,
that were becoming stronger. Larsson considered them dangerous, being afraid
that the "intuitive movement" might be derailed, and came to emphasize the
logical and rational features of his theory of intuition. His attitude toward
the concept of intuition changed through the
years.
24. From Matti, G. (2000). Det intuitiva livet: Hans Larssons vision om enhet i
en splittrad tid. Uppsala: Gidlunds Förlag. In Swedish:
- Page 98
Kant -- liksom hans efterföljare inom den tyska
transcendentalfilosofin, framför allt Fichte -- blev en av Larssons
främsta filosofiska influenser. -
- Page 121
På
ålderdomens höst avslöjar Larsson i ett opublicerat manuskript
att hans primära syfte i intuitionsfrågan har varit att utarbeta "en
metod att arbeta på livets alla områden". -
- Page
159
År 1908 skrev Larsson i uppsatsen "Det intuitiva omdömets
pålitlighet": "Den intuition som är rädd för klarheten
är en gottköpsintuition, och med sådan drives mycket ofog i
våra dagar." -
- Page 161-163
Det finns motsatta linjer i Larssons
intuitionsfilosofi; den handlings- och viljeinriktade livsfilosofiska linjen,
och den rationella "finlogiska" linjen. För Larsson själv fanns
här ingen motsägelse, men att vid tiden kring första
världskriget då handling, vilja och "liv" so ofta ställdes i
skarp kontrast till den "handlingsdödande reflexionen" [cf. paralysis]
försöka hålla ihop dessa båda tendenser i en syntes hade
uppenbarligen sina problem. I sin sista skrift Postscriptum (1944)
uppmärksammar Larsson den urspårade avart av den "intuitiva
rörelsen" som den nazistiska "filosofin" eller
världsåskådningen innebar: "[d]en intuition som åberopar
sig på någon sorts omedelbar visshet, för vilken man inte
är skyldig ge skäl, inbjuder till allsköns godtycke. För min
del ville jag legitimera intuitionen och på samma gång avböja
intuitionsofoget -- som i våra dagar blivit ganska världsfarligt."
Larsson var alltså att den intuitiva rörelsen "än en gång"
skulle urarta; det var den "nya romantiken" han hade i åtanke. Den
intuitiva rörelsen under romantiken hade förfallit till
"konturlös åskådning" dekadent "stämningsdyrkan", och
politiskt sett i reaktionärt bakåtsträvande. Den hade
fördjupat livsfrågorna men fört med sig svammel,
gottköpsoriginalitet och reaktion. -
- Page 174
John Landquist
menar att Larsson inte dragit de naturliga konsekvenserna av sina analyser
eftersom "de skulle leda direkt in i metafysiken och spränga den agnostiska
begränsningen". Intuitionen måste ha en metafysisk förankring. I
sitt kanske mest betydande arbete, Människokunskap från 1920,
utvecklar Landquist sin egen, av Bergson inspirerade, intuitionslära. Han
fogar till skillnad mot Larsson intuitionen i ett historiefilosofiskt
sammanhang. -
- Page 188
Formen är ena sidan av innehållet
och vice versa, relationen mellan kvantitet och kvalitet är likadan.
Samstämmighetskravet är därmed identiskt med "kravet på
förnuft". Denna föreställning är förenad med
teleologisk uppfattning i Hegelsk anda. Spencer och Hegel hade enligt Larsson
båda med sina egna ord formulerat en allomfattande utvecklingsformel och
det är ingen tillfällighet att Larsson avslutar "Reflexioner för
dagen" med att också anknyta till
Hegel.
25. From Heidegger, M. (1968). What is called thinking? New York: Harper &
Row. (Trans. by J. Glenn Gray. Orig. Was Heisst Denken? Tübingen: Max
Niemeyer, 1954):
- (Page 71) A dialogue of Plato -- the Phaedrus, for example, the conversation
on Beauty -- can be interpreted in totally different spheres and respects,
according to totally different implications and problematics. This multiplicity
of possible interpretations does not discredit the strictness and the thought
content. For all true thought remains open to more than one interpretation
-- and this by reason of its nature. Nor is this multiplicity of possible
interpretations merely the residue of a still unachieved formal-logic univocity
which we properly ought to strive but did not attain. Rather, multiplicity
of meanings is the element in which all thought must move in order to be strict
thought. To use an image: to a fish, the depths and expanses of its waters,
the currents and quiet pools, warm and cold layers are the element of its
multiple mobility. If the fish is deprived of the fullness of its element,
if it is dragged on the dry sand, then it can only wriggle, twitch, and die.
Therefore, we always must seek out thinking, and its burden of thought, in
the element of its multiple meanings, else everything will remain closed to
us.
-
- If we take up one of Plato's dialogues, and scrutinize and judge
its "content" in keeping with the ways in which sound common sense forms its
ideas - something that happens all too often and too easily -- we arrive at the
most curious views, and finally at the conviction that Plato must have been a
great muddlehead; because we find -- and this is indeed correct -- that not a
single one of Plato's dialogues arrives at a palpable, unequivocal result which
sound common sense could, as the saying goes, hold on to. As if sound common
sense -- the last resort of those who are by nature envious of thinking -- as if
this common sense whose soundness lies in its immunity to any problematic, had
ever...(->p.72)
26. From Plato. (1961). Plato: The collected dialogues. Princeton: Princeton
Univ. Press - Böllingen. (ed. from Epis. VII 343c-344c):
- Now in cases where as a result of bad training we are not even accustomed
to look for the real essence of anything but are satisfied to accept what
confronts us in the phenomenal presentations, we are not rendered by each
other–the examined by the examiners who have the ability to handle the
four [approaches to knowledge and knowledge itself: name, definition, image,
and knowledge] with dexterity and to subject them to examinations. In those
cases, however, where we demand answers and proofs in regard to the fifth
entity [the object of knowledge itself, or true reality], anyone who pleases
among those who have the skill of confutation gains the victory and makes
most of the audience think that the man who was first to speak of write or
answer has no acquaintance with the matters of which he attempts to write
or speak. Sometimes they are unaware that it is not the mind of the writer
or speaker that fails in the test, but rather the character of the four–since
that is naturally defective. Natural intelligence and a good memory are equally
powerless to aid the man who has not an inborn affinity with the subject.
The study of virtue and vice must be accompanied by an inquiry into what is
false and true of existence in general and must be carried on by constant
practice throughout a long period. Hardly after practicing detailed comparisons
of names and definitions and visual and other sense perceptions, after scrutinizing
them in benevolent disputation by the use of question and answer without jealousy,
at last in a flash understanding blazes up, and the mind, as it exerts all
its powers to the limit of human capacity, is flooded with light. For this
reason no serious man will ever think of writing about serious realities for
the general public so as to make them a prey to envy and perplexity.
27. From Aristotle. (1984). The complete work of Aristotle: The revised Oxford
translation (2 Volumes). Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press. (Ed. by Jonathan
Barnes. ISBN 0-691-09950-2.) Vol 2: Nicomachean Ethics:
- PARAGRAPH 1106 a36
Excellence, then, is a state concerned with choice,
lying in a mean relative to us, this being determined by reason and in the way
in which the man of practical wisdom would determine. -
- PARAGRAPH 1139
a18
The excellence of a thing is relative to its proper function. Now there
are three things in the soul which control action and truth -- sensation,
thought, desire. Of these sensation originates no action. And what affirmation
and negation are in thinking, pursuit and avoidance are in desire; so that since
moral excellence is a state concerned with choice, and choice is deliberate
desire, therefore both the reasoning must be true and the desire right, if the
choice is to be good, and the latter must pursue just what the former asserts.
Now this kind of intellect and of truth is practical; of the intellect which is
contemplative, not practical nor productive, the good and bad states are truth
and falsity; while of the part which is practical and intellectual the good
state is truth in agreement with right desire. -
- PARAGRAPH 1139
a32
The origin of action -- its efficient, not its final cause -- is choice, and
that of choice is desire and reasoning with a view to an end. This is why
choice cannot exist without thought or intellect or without a moral state;
for good action and its opposite cannot exist without a combination of intellect
and character. Intellect itself, however, moves nothing, but only intellect
which aims at an end and is practical; for this rules the productive intellect
as well, since every one who makes makes for an end, and that which is made
is not an end in the unqualified sense (but only relative to something, i.e.
of something) --only that which is done is that; for a good action
is an end, and desire aims at this. Hence choice is either desiderative thought
or intellectual desire, and such an origin of action is man. The function
of both the intellectual parts, then, is truth.
-
- PARAGRAPH 1139 b15
The
states by virtue of which the soul possesses truth by way of affirmation or
denial are five in number, i.e. art, knowledge, practical wisdom, philosophic
wisdom, comprenhension; for belief and opinion may be mistaken. Regarding what
knowledge is, we all suppose that what we know is not capable of being
otherwise; of things capable of being otherwise we do not know, when they have
passed outside our observation whether they exist or not. Therefore the object
of knowledge is of necessity. Therefore it is eternal. -
- PARAGRAPH 1140
a1
Among things that can be otherwise are included both things made and
things done; making and acting are different; so that the reasoned state of
capacity to act is different from the reasoned state of capacity to make. Nor
are they included one in the other; for neither is acting making not making
acting. Now since building [cf. design, architecture] is an art and is
essentially a reasoned state of capacity to make, and there is neither art that
is not such a state nor any such state that is not an art, art is identical with
a state of capacity to make, involving a true course of reasoning. Art is a
state concerned with making, involving a true course of
reasoning. -
- PARAGRAPH 1140 a24
Regarding practical wisdom we shall
get at the truth by considering who are the persons we credit with it: the man
with it is able to deliberate well about what is good and expedient for himself,
not in some particular respect, but about what conduce to the good life in
general. This is shown by the fact that we credit men with practical wisdom in
some particular respect when they have calculated well -- are capable of
deliberating --with a view to some good end which is one of those that are not
the object of any art...So, practical wisdom cannot be knowledge, because that
which can be done is capable of being otherwise, nor art because action and
making are different kinds of thing. It is a true and reasoned state of capacity
to act with regard to the things that are good or bad for man. For while making
has an end other than itself, action cannot; for good action itself is its
end... Practical wisdom must be a reasoned and true state of capacity to act
with regard to human goods. But further, while there is such a thing as
excellence in art, there is no such thing as excellence in practical wisdom; and
in art he who errs willingly is preferable, but in practical wisdom as in the
excellences his is the reverse. Plainly, then, practical wisdom is an excellence
[virtue] and not an art. -
- PARAGRAPH 1141 a11
Some people are wise in
general, not in some particular field or in any other limited respect. Therefore
[philosophical] wisdom must be plainly be the most finished of the forms of
knowledge. It follows that the wise man must not only know what follows from the
first principles, but must also possess truth about them. Therefore wisdom must
be comprenhension combined with knowledge. It is to that which observes well the
various matters concerning itself that one ascribes practical wisdom. This is
why we say that some even of the lower animals have practical wisdom, viz. those
which are found to have a power of foresight with regard to their own life. It
is evident that wisdom and the art of politics cannot be the same; for if the
state of mind concerned with a man's own interests is to be called wisdom, there
will be many wisdoms; there will ne be one concerned with the good of all
animals, but a different wisdom about the good of each species.
-
- PARAGRAPH 1141 b15
Practical wisdom is not concerned with
universals only -- it must also recognize the particulars, for it is practical,
and practice is concerned with particulars. This is why some who do not know,
and especially those who have experience, are more practical than others who
know. Now pratical wisdom is concerned with action; therefore one should have
both forms of it (universal and particular), or the particular in preference to
the universal. Here too, there must be a controlling kind....Political wisdom
and practical wisdom are the same state of mind, but to be them is not the same.
Of the wisdom concerned with the city, the practical wisdom which plays a
controlling part is legislative wisdom, while that which is related to this as
particulars to their universal is known by the general name of "political
wisdom"; this has do do with action and deliberation, for a decree is a thing to
be carried out in the form of an individual act. This is why the exponents of
this art are alone said to take part in politics; for these alone do things as
manual labourers do things....Practical wisdom also is identified especially
with that form of it which is concerned with a man himself -- with the
individual; and this is known by the general name "practical wisdom""; of the
other kinds one is called household management [economics], another legislation,
the third politics, and the last one part is called deliberative athe other
judicial. Now knowing what is good for oneself will be one kind of knowledge,
but is very different from the other kinds; and the man who knows and concerns
himself with his own interests is thought to have practical wisdom, while
politicians are thought to be busybodies. From those who seek their own good,
and consider that one ought to do so, has come the view that such men have
practical wisdom; yet perhaps one's own good cannot exist without some household
management, nor without a form of government. -
- PARAGRAPH 1142
a23
That practical wisdom is not knowledge is evident; for it is concerned
with the ultimate particular fact, since the thing to be done is of this nature.
It is opposed, then, to comprehension; for comprehension is of the definitions,
for which no reason can be given. -
- PARAGRAPH §1143 a25
All the
states we have considered converge, on the same point; for when we speak of
judgment and understanding [learning] and practical wisdom and comprenhension we
credit the same people with possessing judgment and comprehension and with
having practical wisdom and understanding. For all these faculties deal with
ultimates, i.e. particulars. Comprehension is concerned with the ultimates in
both directions; for both the primary definitions and the ultimates are objects
of comprenhension and not of argument, and in demonstrations comprehension
grasps the unchangeable and primary definitions, while in practical reasoning it
grasps the last and contingent fact, i.e. the second proposition. For these are
the starting-points of that for the sake of which, since the universals are
reached from the particulars; of these therefore we must have perception, and
this is comprehension....Hence comprenhension is both beginning and end; for
demonstrations are from these and about these. Therefore we ought to attend to
the undemonstrated sayings and opinions of experienced and older people or of
people of practical wisdom not less that to demonstrations; for because
experience has given them an eye they see aright. -
- PARAGRAPH 1144
a6
The function of man is achieved only in accordance with practical wisdom
as well as with moral excellence; for excellence makes the aim right, and
practical wisdom the things leading to it...But it is impossible to be
practically wise without being good, and it is not possible to be good in the
strict sense without practical wisdom. In this way we may also refute the
dialectical argument whereby it might be contended that the excellences exist in
separation from each other. This is possible in respect of the natural
excellences, but not in respect of those in respect of which a man is called
without qualification good; for with the presence of the one quality, practical
wisdom, will be given all the excellences. The choice will not be right without
practical wisdom any more than without excellence; for the one determines the
end and the other makes us do the things that lead to the end. But again, it is
not supreme over wisdom, i.e. over the superior part of us, any more than the
art of medicine is over health; for it does not use it but provides for its
coming into being; it issues orders, then, for its sake, but not for it.
Further, to maintain its supremacy would be like saying that the art of politics
rules the gods because it isues orders about all the affairs of the
state.
28. From Pierre Aubenque's book "La prudence chez Aristote: avec un appendice
sur la prudence chez Kant" [Phronesis according to Aristotle: with an appendix
on phronesis according to Kant], Quadrige/PUF, 1993 (1961). Ref. also to the
documentation of Kristo Ivanov' seminar 15 October 1997 at Umeå
university's dept. of informatics, his free edited translation, and to Kristo's
essay (www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/chinese.html)."Strategy and design for
information technology":
- Pages 39-45
The definition, whatever it is, of the essence of prudence
presupposes the existence of the prudent man, and the description of this
existence. It is not satisfactory to determine prudence as a specification of
virtue [excellence] in general, for the essential reason that the existence of
the prudent man is already implicated by the general definition of virtue. It is
enough, to get convinced, to refer to the general definition of virtue:
"Excellence, then, is a state concerned with choice, lying in a mean relative to
us, being determined by reason and in a way in which the man of practical wisdom
would determine" [Aristotle, §1106 b36]. Let's focus, in this definition,
on the role accorded to phronimos, a role whose abusive character has not
always been sufficiently emphasized. Virtue consists in acting according to the
right mean, and the criterium of the right mean is reason, or the right rule.
But what is the right rule? Aristotle does not give us any means for recognizing
it, if not the appeal to the judgment of the prudent man. This would not be a
problem if the prudent man obtained his authority from wisdom or from science,
whose instrument it would then be: because it is the universal which then would
express itself through his voice. But the prudent man is neither a sage nor
scientist: not having any familiarity with the transcendent, he puts himself at
the level of the particular and fixes at each one the right mean which responds
to its particularity. The prudent man knows what is good for us. He is the
living bearer of the right rule of reason. The phronimos would be then
the inheritor of the platonic philosopher-king...But where there are no more
Ideas, the prudent man finds himself referred only to his own capabilities, to
only his experience...The platonic leader did not dispense of law, because it
was in itself bearer of a science of a higher order than any law...If, for
Plato, law was a substitute for the infallibility of science, for Aristotle it
is equity which is a corrective for the fallibility of the law...The equitable
man must possess the highest level the virtue [excellence] of prudence. Moral
virtue consists in applying the standard determined by the prudent man. It is no
more the good man who has his eyes fixed on the Ideas, but it is we who have our
eyes fixed on the good man. -
- At this point, Aristotle seems to return,
beyond the intellectualisme of Socrates and Plato, to some achaic ideal of the
heroe, who imposes himself less by his knowledge that by his deeds, or simply
his ardour.
-
- Pages 132-139. Plato and the Stoics emphasized the
importance of the (good) will at the expense of its practical workings and
results vis-a-vis to unforeseen obstacles to implementation and failure. In
doing so Plato reminded the importance of subordinating the means to the ends
but paid scanty attention to the insufficiency of the means. "It is easier to
give a flute [or a computer] to somebody who already knows how to play or use
it, than to teach play and use to somebody who has the artifact". The technology
of production is subordinated to that of use. That explained that man could do
what is agreeable without doing what he wanted, like avoiding to take a drug
despite wanting health. The will to the end is what gives meaning to means,
turning the disagreeable into good. This implied, however, that failure would be
mostly attributed to forgetfulness or weakness of the will, or complacency in
the choice of isolated means, and therefore injustly attributed only to the
human as guilt. Aristotle reconsidered the relation between means and ends.
Assuming, as Socrates and Plato, that the will or apparent will can by nature
only be good [cf. today's attribution of crime to faulty information and
education of the criminal] he established that there was no virtue or merit in a
good will, and an important part of the problem consisted in achieving some good
in terms of at least satisficing results by the use of available means according
to the doctrine or practical knowledge of prudence-phronesis [deliberation plus
choice]. [Cf. also Aristole's preference for functional and teleological
explanations over deterministic ones, and refer to Churchman's The Design of
Inquiring Systems, kap. 3 and 10.] A bad will or will to evil was considered to
be a monstrous exception [against good nature, akin to Taoist immanence] and was
relegated outside the area of ethics [cf. today's depth psychology]. Evil and
failure tended then be regarded as the consequence of not being able to rightly
deliberate or judge [överlägga med omdöme] and choose or decide
[besluta] on the convenient means. This led in turn to an emphasis on
instrumental reason as technology (of means) and an unintended weakenig of
personal responsibility in that evil was considered to be technical
insufficiency. The new scheme raised also the problem of the conflict between
means and ends as when a good end can be achieved by bad means but Aristotle did
not perceive the problem: there was no Machiavelism but, rather, only clumsiness
in the choice of means. Ethics was limited by the fundamental randomness of
birth [cf. monstruosity against nature, and racial eugenics] and by the residual
randomness of implementation that gets lost in the indetermination of matter
[cf. shift and drift requiring skilled creative improvisation]. The core of
ethics is then centered not in the absolute of the will but rather in the choice
of means. The philosopher, more than the historian can only regret that these
relative notions of good and evil are not yet emancipated from the "technical"
notions of success and failure. This emancipation was eventually made possible
by a revelation that Aristotle like other Greeks lacked, namely about the
existence of a perverted will, and the consequent reflection about the essence
and meaning of sin.
29. From Kant, I. (1790/1987). Critique of judgement. Indianapolis/Cambridge:
Hackett. (Trans. with an introduction by Werner S. Pluhar. Foreword by Mary J.
Gregor.):
- Translator's introduction page lxxxvi
In a syllogism the power of
judgment subsumes the particular under som universal (i.e. under some principle)
supplied by understanding and thereby ebables reason to make an inference from
that universal to the particular. In the same way feeling must be considered an
independent member among the three general mental powers because it mediates
between the cognitive power (in general) and the power of desire. Feeling
mediates between the other two mental powers insofar as both the lower power of
desire (the will as influenced by sense) and the higher (the will as
determinable by its own moral law) connect a pleasure with nature: the lower
connects this pleasure with nature cognized as it already is; the higher, with
nature cognized as it (morally) ought to be. Thus a twofold systematicity is
established: among the higher cognitive powers and among the mental powers in
general. Moreover, because understanding legislates in the domain of the concept
of nature (i.e. in the domain of the theoretical cognitive power), and reason
legislates in the domain of the concept of freedom (i.e. in the domain of the
power of desire), the twofold systematicity can be enhanced further if it can be
established that judgment, the mediator of the higher cognitive powers,
similarly legislates to feeling, the mediator of the mental powers in
general. -
- Translators introducion page ciii
The power of judgment is
to mediate between the real of nature and the realm of freedom. But judgment's
concept of nature's subjective purposiveness is especially "suitable" for
mediating between these two realms only if no objective purposiveness
(purposiveness with a purpose) has been based on it, i.e. only if the subjective
purposiveness is merely subjective, a purposiveness without a purpose, and hence
a purposiveness as judged aesthetically. For only such purposiveness without a
purpose is "analogous" to or "symbolic" of the supersensible form that the moral
law enjoins us to impose on nature. -
- Page 178
Even though mechanical
and fine art are very different from each other, since the first is based merely
on diligence and learning but the second on genius, yet there is no fine art
that does not have as its essential condition something mechanical, which can be
encompassed by rules and complied with, and hence has an element of academic
correctness. For something must be thought, as purpose, since otherwise the
product cannot be ascribed to any art at all, but would be a mere product of
chance. But directing the work to a purpose requires determinate rules that one
is not permitted to renounce. Now since originality of talent is one essential
component (though not the only one) of the character of genius, shallow minds
believe that the best way to show that they are geniuses in first bloom is by
renouncing all academic rules of constraint. Genius can only provide rich
material for products of fine art; processing this material and giving it form
requires a talent that is academically trained, so that it may be used in a way
that can stand the test of the power of judgment. But it is utterly ridiculous
for someone to speak and decide like a genius even in matters that require the
most careful rational investigation. -
- Page 196
What is essential in
all fine arts is the form that is purposive or our our observation and judging,
rather than the matter of sensation, i.e. charm or emotion. For the pleasure we
take in purposive form is also culture, and it attunes the spirit to ideas, a so
makes it receptive to more such pleasure and entertainment; in the case of the
matter of sensation, however, the aim is merely enjoyment, which leaves nothing
behind as an idea and makes the spirit dull, the object gradually disgusting,
and the mind dissatisfied with itself and moody because it is conscious that in
reason's judgment its attunement is contrapurposive. Unless we connect the fine
arts with moral ideas, which alone carry with them an independent liking, the
second of the two alternatives just mentioned is their ultimate
fate. -
- Page 228-229
The morally good is the intelligible that taste
has in view, for it is with this intelligible that even our higher cognitive
powers harmonize, and without it contradictions would continueally arise from
the contrast between the nature of these powers and the claims that taste
makes -
- Page 319
Proucing in a rational being an aptitude for purposes
generally (hence in a way that leaves the being free) is culture. Hence only
culture can be the ultimate purpose that we have cause to attribute to nature
with respect to the human species. But not just any culture is adequate for this
ultimate purpose of nature. The culture of skill is indeed the foremost
subjective condition for an aptitude to promote purposes generally; but it is
not adequate to assist the will in the determination and selection of its
purposes, while yet such determination is surely an essential part of our entire
aptitude for purposes, and is the other condition, besides skill, of this
aptitude. This other condition could be called the culture of discipline. It is
negative and consists in the liberation of the will from the despotism of
desires [cf. desiderata], a despotism that rivets us to certain natural things
and renders us unable to do our own selecting; we allow ourselves to be fettered
by the impulses that nature gave us only as guides so that we would not neglect
or even injure our animal characteristics, whereas in fact we are free enough to
tighten or to slacken, to lengthen or to shorten them, as the purposes of reason
require. -
- Page 319-320
As for the culture of skill: it is hard to
develop skill in the human species except by means of inequality among people.
The majority take care, mechanically as it were and without particularly needing
art [cf. design] for this, of the necessities of life of others, who thus have
the ease and leisure to work in science and art, the less necessary ingredients
in culture. The others keep the majority in a state of oppression, hard labor,
and little enjoyment, even though some of the culture of the higher class
gradually spread to the lower also. But on both sides trouble increases with
equal vigor as culture progresses. (The height of this progress, when people's
propensity to strive for what is dispensable begins to interefere with what is
indispensable, is called luxury.) For the lower class the trouble results from
violence from without, for the higher from insatiability within. And yet this
shining misery has to do with the development of man's natural predispositions
and so nature still achieves its own purpose, even if that purpose is not ours.
The formal condition under which nature can alone achieve this final aim is that
constitution of human relations where the impairment to freedom which results
from the mutually conflicting freedom of the individuals is countered by lawful
authority within a whole called civil
society.
30. From Norris, C. What's wrong with postmodernism: Critical theory and the
ends of philosophy . New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1990:
- Page 269-270. Ref. to de Man's account of Schiller and his idea of
'aesthetic education' as a means of transcending the Kantian disjunction between
knowledge (or cognitive truth claims) on the one hand and imagination (or the
power of inward, sympathetic understanding) on the other. Such would be the
end-point of Schiller's redemptive project: 'A wisdom that lies somehow beyond
cognition and self-knowledge, yet can only be reached by ways of the process it
is said to overcome'.[ref. to Paul De Man, Aesthetic formalization, in The
Rhetoric of Romanticism. New York: Columbia University Press, 1984, pp. 263-290,
p. 265]. Aesthetics would thus become the natural home ground for a different,
altogether 'higher' mode of awareness [cf. sense-making] that disowned
the antinomies of Kantian critical reason and claimed to effect a reconciliation
of the various faculties whose separate domains Kant had attempted to delimit.
But the result...is a species of "aesthetic formalisation" which collapses
the difference between ethics (practical reason) and phenomenal cognition,
and thus makes reason entirely subject to the laws or dictates of natural
necessity. The "state" that is being advocated [in Schiller's Letters on
Aesthetic Education] is not just a state of mind or of soul, but a principle
of political value and authority that has its own claims on the shape and the
limits of our freedom [degrees of freedom, freedom of action]. And these claims
are by no means a mere "aberration" or an isolated instance of aesthetic
philosophy overstepping its legitimate domain. On the contrary..."aesthetic
education by no means fails; it succeeds too well, to the point of hiding the
violence that makes it possible"... It is specifically Heidegger's reading of
Kant - a reading that elevates "productive imagination" to a status far
beyond anything envisaged by Kant himself - that this error takes hold of and
opens the way to all manner of aestheticist
confusion.
31. From Ferry, L. Homo aestheticus : The invention of taste in the democratic
age, trans. by Robert de Loaiza. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press,
1993:
- Page 151 (From chapter on "The Nietzschean moment")
By opposition to the
dialectician, who is the theoretical man (learned man or philosopher) animated
always by the will to truth, the artist appears as an aristocratic character.
Still living in the predemocratic world of tradition (for example the "great
Hellenes" before Socrates), he posits values without discussion, without
argument, with authority. The forces he plays with are not reactive: unlike the
truth, they don't need to deny other forces to posit themselves. -
- Page
154-158 (From chapter on "The Nietzschean moment")
In order to apprehend the
presence of "completed metaphysics" in the technologized relation to the world,
we have to take into account the practical aspect of the metaphysics of
subjectivity. Throughout the modern intensification of the essence of
subjectivity as will [to create usable objects], the existent, the totality of
being, has tended more and more to have no reality except as object, manipulable
by the subject under the aspect of accomplishing ends, uniformly at the disposal
of the will [cf. use] whether as instrument or as beings...Kant's
reinterpretation of the I think as an I want, and especially his doctrine of the
autonomy of the will, were decisive steps towards the technic interpretation of
the world that Nietzsche's philosophy makes a theme of. The autonomy of the
will, essential link in the process of the technologization of the real would
not be separated from the ultimate absolutization of the will save for one
mediation, that of the Nietzschean theory of the will to power as the "second to
the last state of the will's development". Along the road from Descartes to
Nietzsche, reason's becoming and its fate will have consisted in no longer
establishing objectives itself, but rather in transforming itself from the
objective reason is attempted to be into purely instrumental reason. The will
is, in parallel fashion, itself no longer assigned to any end. The mastery over
the world no longer aims, as it did with Descartes or the Enlightenment, at
emancipating human beings or at obtaining their happiness; it becomes the quest
for mastery (or brute force) for the sake of mastery (or brute force). It is
thus as a metaphysician that Nietzsche, following a central theme in his
aesthetics, conceptualizes art more in terms of the artist, that is, of the
creator (of his will) than in terms of the work of art itself. His philosophy of
art takes the form of a "physiology", or a theory of the "vital forces" at the
beginning of creative activity. Beauty is nothing other than the wisely unifying
hierarchized (in the "grand style") expression of life's radical multiplicity.
Ultra-individualism, while pursuing the revolutionary values of the individual
emancipation from tradition, consecrates innovation as the supreme criterion of
the aesthetic judgment, and thus causes the latter to fall into the sphere of
historicity. -
- Page 257-259 (From chapter on "The problem of
ethics")
We are witnessing a mutation linked to the momentous rise of
democratic individualism. Several studies have shown how hedonistic and
narcissistic ideologies have taken hold of traditional moral questions. The key
word would no longer be Greek excellence, and even less Kantian merit, but
authenticity. The main thing is no longer to come up against imperative external
norms, but to arrive at the expression of one's personality, at the development
and opening up of the self...The problem with the ethics of the contemporaries
and with the consecration of the authentic as such is that reference to the very
idea of limit seems to fade away, delegitimized as it is by the imperious
demands made by individual self-cultivation and by the right to difference. When
it is "forbidden to forbid", dogmatism becomes the supreme sin, and tends to be
confused with the very thing the moderns held to be the truth of reason. Hatred
of rationalism blossoms upon the ethics of authenticity, and criticism of the
former, until recently the prerrogative of contemporary philosophy, now finds
echoes even in the scientists' universe -- witness the success of various essays
on epistemology [cf. relations between science, art and design] that happily
trample on reason.
32. Example (in Swedish) of neglected type social-political and ethical
analysis, in one main Swedish theoretical approach to design: Paulsson, G.,
& Paulsson, N. (1956). Tingens bruk och prägel [Things for everyday use
and life form]. Stockholm: Kooperativa Förbundets Bokförlag, chap on
Nyttoting och livsform. Pages 115-123:
- År 1855 skrev Le Play i sitt arbete Les ouvriers
euroéens – ev av de hörnstenar på vilka den moderna
sociologens lärobyggnad sedan blivit upprest...
- Den konsumenttyp, som
på Le Plays tid var ett undantag, begränsat till ett tunt skikt av
förmögna, har nu blivit regel, tillfinnandes överallt i
Västerlandet i den mån som levnadsstandarden stigit: den i frihet
konsumerande människan. Den fullkomliga omvälvning av den
västerländska människans villkor som ägt rum under de
senaste århundradet kan ses som en ständigt ökad frihet att
konsumera....
- Situationen idag...Guds straffdom över människan
efter syndafallet – "I ditt anletes svett skall du äta ditt
bröd" – börjar i det västerländska samhället att
träda ur kraft ...[philosophy of technology cf. Mitcham &
Grote]....Slutligen har motiven för det personliga sparandet helt
ändrats. Bortsett från de mindre företagen – vilkas
mängd och livsduglighet inte får underskattas – spelar det
personliga ägandet av en egen produktions- och distributionsapparat inte
samma dominerande roll som förr. [vs Marxism, cf KF Kooperativa
Förbundet]. Ägandet är mer eller mindre anonymt, och detta
gäller både privata, kooperativa och allmänna företag. En
människas sociala och ekonomiska avancemang beror nu väsentligen
på hennes personliga duglighet. [cf. Luc Ferry].
- Det frivilliga
sparandet är nu för de flesta inte ett investeringssparande utan ett
konsumtionssparande: för att kunna skaffa sig en egen bostad, för
bosättning, för en semesterresa och liknande...I princip är det
västeuropeiska stadssamhället idag ett enklassigt samhälle med en
enbart av de kontanta existensmedlen begränsad konsumtion.
- Och dock
säger den minsta eftertanke att detta inte får betyda, att alla
människor får konsumera utan omtanke [cf. ethics vs
politics!]....
- Låt oss göra en analys av situationen idag ur
två synpunkter: möjligheten att konsumera och sätten att
konsumera. I jämförelse med äldre tider har för
västerlandets människa knappheten blivit till riklighet,
normtvånget till frihet [cf. Ferry]. Ekonomiskt sett kan man konsumera
förtänksamt eller slösande, socialt sett självständigt
eller ivrigt följande dagens mod [sic!], de förnäma,
filmstjärnorna, etc. Båda synpunkterna kombinerade ge polerna
återhållsamhet och skrytsamhet.
- Man skulle nu begå ett
ödesdigert misstag om man lade sätten att konsumera över
möjligheterna och lät möjligheten till riklighet resultera
i en slösande, skrytsam eller ivrigt följande konsumtionsstil. Det
finns en återhållsam knapphet, en knapphet av ekonomiskt eller
socialt tvång. Det finns också en återhållsamhet i
rikligheten, en återhållsamhet av fritt val [cf. smak, taste]. Den
kan ta en sjuklig form och bli snålhet, men dess normala form är
besinningen.
- Om man nu gör det påstående [ethics?] att den
förtänksamma, återhållsamma, självständiga
konsumtionssättet ut både individens och samhällets synpunkt
är värdefullare än det slösande, skrytsamma och
följande, så grundar det sig på det förhållandet,
att det klasslösa och dynamiska samhället fordrar en fritt
väljande [mot "följande" ≈ följsamma] människa,
för att förbli ett demokratiskt samhället [Kant democracy].
Alternativet blir ett av massrörelser behärskat.
- Mot detta
mönster kan den anmärkningen göras, att det är ett
dygdemönster, som i längden blir tråkigt [cf. ethics and Kant
pleasure vs happiness]. De flesta människor har behov av
förströelser, motsatsen till förtänksamhet och
återhållsamhet [?]. Men det finns två slags av rekreation. Det
första är vad man kallar "tomma nöjen" som består av flykt
från livet, en kompensation för det som på ett eller annat
sätt blivit en övermäktigt [cf. marxism vs chriatianity
martyrdom]. Den andra är nöjen som består av ett nytt slag av
aktivitet, ett görande för görandets egen skull. Dit hör
leken, filuftslivet, och annan fysisk rekreation samt den estetiska aktiviteten
och kontemplationen. För den människa som har en
självständig livsstil [cf. the WILL vs ethics & taste] kan det
åvabringas [sic!] en fin och livsbefordrande balans mellan nödtorft
och rekreation. För människan med den slösande, skrytsamma
livsstilen blir detta omöjligt [cf. Ferry hierarchical non-democratic]. Det
är för närvarande så, att inom viktiga sektorer det
på marknaden [market] erbjudna sortimentet av varor passar bättre
för den ivrigt följsamma än för den självständiga
konsumtionen. Genom hjälp av massmedier, såsom annonsering,
illustrerade tidskrifter filmer och liknande får dessa ting en stor makt
[vs marxism] över människorna. De enskilda individernas
handlingsmönster utsätts för ständig inverkan från
dem. I praktiken betyder detta att varusortimentet också framkallar en
sådan konsumtion. [cf. Intenet-commerce].
- För att
åstadkomma en självständig konsumtion fordras två saker.
Den ena är att att personliga handlingsmönster bygges upp [cf. ethics
education religion?]. varvid användning av de kulturella institutioner som
är personlighetsberikande — litteraturen, konsten, musiken,
vetenskapen — [cf. university, Ellen Key, Hegel] verkar befordrande,
kanske rent av är nödvändig. En människa utan delaktighet
[cf. participation, medbestämmande MBL]. En människa utan delaktighet
i någon av dessa driver som ett rö för vinden. Ju större
delaktighet, ju större självständighet i handlande. [cf.
påvens i SAF-boken vs. Gustav LeBons Le Bon & democracy]. Den andra
är att det verkligen finns varor som tillfredsställer denna
konsumtionskrav och verkarbefordrande på den [OBSERVERA cf. positivism of
data vs uses of data, administration vs. politics ≈ Stolterman?]. Detta
är den monderna konstindustrins kärnproblem. Det är inte dess
enda men dess viktigaste. Balansen mellan vardagsvara och ting som är
gjorda enbart för nöjet att göras och betraktas är
följdproblem, som lätt får sin riktiga formulering, då
kärnproblemet är löst.
-
- Det som skett i de resonemang som
genomgår denna skrift är att tingens form aldrig betraktas isolerad
utan alltid sätts i relation till dess bruk. [cf. pragmatism]. Det är
sålunda förhållandet mellan tingen och människan som
gjorts till huvudfråga. Det är därigenom som vi har kommit fram
till de "moraliska" [sic!]
- [s. 122] konsumtionsproblem som nyss behandlats.
Först genom att klargöra arten av förhållandet mellan ett
ting och den människa som skall bruka det, kan jag få en uppfattning
om detta tings värde.
- Ur detta perspektiv är det lämpligt att
kasta en blick på funktionalismens ideologi. Funktionalismen kan
både ses som slutet på en historisk epok och som början
på en ny. Den drev till sin sista konsekvens de tre principer som
uppställdes för arikitekturens och konstindustrins sanering redan vid
artonhundratalets slut mot laisser-faire industrialismen och historismen.
För att befria tingen från de falska symbolvärden [o OBS] som
låg i stilefterhärmning och materialimitation uppställdes som
ledfyr sanningen [OBS] i material, teknik och funtion. Funktionalismen
sökte göra denna sanning total. Dess mål var att nå den
definitiva formen hos kategori efter kategori av tingen. Hade detta lyckats,
skulle konstindustrins sista kapitel ha skrivits och människorna för
att framtid levt i den miljön.
- Man förbisåg att denna
sanning inte var hela sanningen. Man fattade begreppet funktion för
trångt [cf. SYSTEM-functional vs teleological classes]. Man
överdimensionerade det praktiska och estetiska men trängde i
realiteten inte riktigt in i den sociala funktionen. Det är den som ger
hela atmosfären i den tingens värld med vilken vi omger oss, det
är den som ger det det dagliga livet dess stil [STYLE-TASTE]. Genom
funktionalismens utradering av alla de formlögner i vilka tingen varit
insvepta, blev den början till en ny epok. Det blev möjligt att bygga
upp nya och för vår livssituation riktiga symbolvärden hos
vår fysiska omgivning. Och ur denna synpunkt har de veka viljor [THE WILL]
varit ute på irrvägar, som försökte skapa en "moderat
funktionalism"genom att sätta på diverse slag av broderier. De valde
romantikens [romanticism] flykt istället för det konstruktiva arbetet
[≈≠construvtivism]. Det är osckså lämpligt att ur
nusituationens synpunkt vända blicken mot andra hållet: tingen hos
den värld som levde utestlutande av de lokala resurserna, som nu
hemslöjden söker bevara. Det är ett angeläget ärende
för en hushållning som genombryter de lokalt begränsade
resurserna att rädda över de av den primitivares som var bättre.
Hemslöjdens ting gjordes uteslutande för bruksvärdets skull och
därmed fick de av sig själv kvalitet [≈≠
snickarglädje]. De ekonomiska faktorerna som måste spela sin stora
roll vid tillverkning för en marknad gör, som välbekant är,
att kvalitetsspörsmålet inte alltid är det ledande.
- Vi ser
idag att de tekniska och ekonomiska framstegen ökat människans
livsmöjligheter, men vi vet också att vi i vissa avseenden fått
köpa dem dyrt. De psykosomatiska sjukdomarnas ökning på grund av
jäkt och oro
- s. 123
- har gett läkare anledning att tala om
hela samhällen som sjuka. Socialvården på sitt språk om
samma sak: att den ekonomiska och tekniska förbättringen inte för
alla är en moralisk [ETHICS] förbättring.
- Sedan
människan gjort det möjligt för sig att skaffa sig nyttigheter
som för ett släktled sedan skulle ansetts som ett privilegium för
ett fåtal, blir det nu hennes nästa uppgift att rätt [RIGHT]
begagna dessa nyttigheter.
- Vad är i sammanhanget rätt? [Ethics]
Givetvis inte att den ena saken för man ha och den andra bör man
undvika, utan förmåga till val i en självbestämd
livsförings tjänst. [Kant; philosophy of technology Mitcham &
Grote] Att de stora konsumentgrupperna gpr in för en självbestämd
konsumtionsstil [STYLE?] innebär att betonandet av en varas praktiska och
estetiska funktion blir en social faktor [sic], en allmänt accepterad
social norm [sic]. Härigenom kan en andlig och kroppslig hälsa skapas,
i nöd såväl lust, och människan fulla personlighet
därigenom uttryckas. Ingetdera kan ske utan sådan hushållning
med markerna och vattendragen [ecology environment] att de inte
förstörs utan förbättras, och utan sådan
hushållning med den med konst gjorda, fysiska omgivningen att dess
praktiska, sociala och estetiska karaktär ger människan fred med livet
och uppväcker sinnet för vad som befordrar det och vad som
försör det.
- Alla gjorda ting är gjorda för att brukas
[use, usage, pragmatism?]. Det finns inte en enda nyttoting, som kan
förstås om det förs ut ur sitt sammanhang med sitt bruk,
praktiskt, socialt, estetiskt. Det finns å andra sidan inte någon
mänsklig aktivitet utan tillhörande materiella nyttoting. En
snedbelastning av förhållandet mellan människan och tingen kan
vara lika skadlig som en bristande balans i biologiskt avseende genom en
felaktig kost eller psykiskt genom trycket av en olämplig social
miljö.
- Valet av varor är ett val av
livstil.
33. From Fides et Ratio. Encyclical letter . Rome, 1998:
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_15101998_fides-et-ratio_en.html
§§85-87, 97-98 also in
http://www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/PerspSem2000.html:
- This insistence on the need for a close relationship of continuity between
contemporary philosophy and the philosophy developed in the Christian tradition
is intended to avert the danger which lies hidden in some currents of thought
which are especially prevalent today. It is appropriate, I think, to review
them, however briefly, in order to point out their errors and the consequent
risks for philosophical work. The first goes by the name of eclecticism, by
which is meant the approach of those who, in research, teaching and
argumentation, even in theology, tend to use individual ideas drawn from
different philosophies, without concern for their internal coherence, their
place within a system or their historical context. They therefore run the risk
of being unable to distinguish the part of truth of a given doctrine from
elements of it which may be erroneous or ill-suited to the task at hand. An
extreme form of eclecticism appears also in the rhetorical misuse of
philosophical terms to which some theologians are given at times. Such
manipulation does not help the search for truth and does not train reason --
whether theological or philosophical -- to formulate arguments seriously and
scientifically. The rigorous and far-reaching study of philosophical doctrines,
their particular terminology and the context in which they arose, helps to
overcome the danger of eclecticism and makes it possible to integrate them into
theological discourse in a way appropriate to the task. Eclecticism is an error
of method, but lying hidden within it can also be the claims of
historicism.
-
- Faced with contemporary challenges in the social,
economic, political and scientific fields, the ethical conscience of people is
disoriented. Many of the problems of the contemporary world stem from a crisis
of truth. Once the idea of a universal truth about the good, knowable by human
reason, is lost, inevitably the notion of conscience also changes.
Conscience is no longer considered in its prime reality as an act of a person's
intelligence, the function of which is to apply the universal knowledge of the
good in a specific situation and thus to express a judgment about the right
conduct to be chosen here and now. Instead, there is a tendency to grant to the
individual conscience the prerogative of independently determining the criteria
of good and evil and then acting accordingly. Such an outlook is quite congenial
to an individualist ethic, wherein each individual is faced with his own truth
different from the truth of
others.
34. From. Veritatis Splendor. Encyclical letter . Rome, 1993:
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_06081993_veritatis-splendor_en.html,
also in also http://www.informatik.umu.se/~kivanov/PerspSem2000.html:
- Paragraph 32. Certain currents of modern thought have gone so far as to
exalt freedom to such an extent that it becomes an absolute, which would then be
the source of values. This is the direction taken by doctrines which have lost
the sense of the transcendent or which are explicitly atheist. The individual
conscience is accorded the status of a supreme tribunal of moral judgment which
hands down categorical and infallible decisions about good and evil. To the
affirmation that one has a duty to follow one's conscience is unduly added the
affirmation that one's moral judgment is true merely by the fact that it has its
origin in the conscience. But in this way the inescapable claims of truth
disappear, yielding their place to a criterion of sincerity, authenticity and
"being at peace with oneself", so much so that some have come to adopt a
radically subjectivistic conception of moral judgment. As is immediately
evident, the crisis of truth is not unconnected with this development. Once the
idea of a universal truth about the good, knowable by human reason, is lost,
inevitably the notion of conscience also changes. Conscience is no longer
considered in its primordial reality as an act of a person's intelligence, the
function of which is to apply the universal knowledge of the good in a specific
situation and thus to express a judgment about the right conduct to be chosen
here and now. Instead, there is a tendency to grant to the individual conscience
the prerogative of independently determining the criteria of good and evil and
then acting accordingly. Such an outlook is quite congenial to an individualist
ethic, wherein each individual is faced with his own truth, different from the
truth of others. Taken to its extreme consequences, this individualism leads to
a denial of the very idea of human nature. These different notions are at the
origin of currents of thought which posit a radical opposition between moral law
and conscience, and between nature and
freedom.
35. CONCLUDING REFLECTION:
- In English: The "old professor" wishes to thank all the students and colleagues
who taught him humility by reminding him that as it is greater to love than
to be loved, so it is possibly greater to read than to be read! It would also
upgrade the value of educating compared to doing "research"
-
- In Swedish: Den "gamle professorn" vill tacka alla de studenter och medarbetare
som lärt honom ödmjukhet genom att påminna honom om att, liksom
det är större att älska än att bli älskad, så
är det möjligen större att han läser än att han blir
läst! Det torde också uppvärdera undervisning eller bildning
i förhållande till "forskning".