PRESUPPOSITIONS IN
INFORMATION SYSTEMS DESIGN:
FROM SYSTEMS TO NETWORKS AND
CONTEXTS?
Commentary to
"Exploring the intellectual structures of information
systems development: A
social action theoretic analysis", paper by R. Hirschheim, H.K. Klein, and
K. Lyytinen. Pre-print version. In Accounting,
Management and Information Technologies, (renamed Information &
Organization), 6, 1996
by Kristo Ivanov
Ume University, Department
of Informatics, S-901 87 UME (Sweden).
Phone +46 90 166030, Fax +46
90 166550, Email:
kivanovATinformatikDOTumuDOTse
Abstract and summary
What seems to be a main
conclusion of the commented paper, the need for pluralism in ISD research, can
be framed as being the original problem that the application of social action
theory cannot grapple with. Pluralism is questioned in terms of its meaning in
political science, and in face of the
elusiveness of the central concept of orientation. The call for
pluralism ignores both political and ethical realities of power versus justice
and love in the Christian tradition. The meaning of the goal of the paper as
being "purely generative and analytic" is thereby also questioned, as
well as its purpose to explain and understand . Its merit is mainly that it
covers other concerns than the purely technical ones, and that it can be used
as an ordered bibliographical source for the design of academic readings. In
this respect the bibliography must be completed with more references to technology,
human-computer interaction, computer supported cooperative work, design, and
privacy as related to justice, power and profitability. Ultimate explanation
and understanding of information systems development requires research on its
presuppositions including paradigmatic limitations of social action theory as
compared with other approaches. This includes the present unfortunate shift
from systems thinking towards learning and networking, where the latter
includes conversational sense-making, argumentation, and accomodation or
negotiation.
Conclusions of the commented
paper
In view of the apparent
complexity of the paper, a frontal approach is to stick right away to its
conclusions in order to try to grasp what is most worthy to be commented.
The authors realize that one
dominant paradigm guides IS research, namely the one based on the
empirical-analytical approach with its unstated identity och relation with an
"instrumental orientation". This paradigm favors control over other
valuable primary orientations: strategic, communicative, and discursive. The
text exhorts the reader claiming that "IS researchers should exhibit more
tolerance towards adherents of different research orientations. This includes a
claim to equitable distribution of research resources among different
traditions. The means must be found for stimulating substantive debate among
different paradigms".
It seems to me that the
conclusions are indeed the statement of the original problem that one would
expect the paper to have addressed as its primary concern, to begin with. It is
indeed a pacific point that there is a great diversity of research problems and
approaches in the field. Depending upon what one should mean by
"explanation", a question which is not really addressed in the paper,
it is also a pacific point that if the situation is what it is, there must be
some serious causes for it, in the Aristotelian sense of cause that includes
motives.(1) The real problem is, then, to understand why one or two particular
orientations or, rather, researchers, dominate over the other ones. It is also
a question of how orientations relate to research paradigms, why some dominant
researchers do not show more tolerance towards researchers with other
orientations, whether debate will do any universal good in view of these
unstated causes for intolerance, and consequently how to find the means for
those particular kinds of debate
or whatever that would do any good.
The paper does not show why
some orientations dominate over the others, and it assumes the remarkably
problematic hypothesis that "actors can change their orientations very
quickly" in ISD, and "actors can also adopt multiple
orientations". It does not acknowledge and specify its own limited
orientation or framework, while drawing very vague and tenuous distinctions or
relations between orientations, paradigms, and the rest. And still it goes
further in its conclusions. It concludes forcefully that the call for a
unifying paradigm is not desirable because that would assumedly reinforce the
dominance of certain paradigms over other orientations, cutting down the variety
of research approaches and limiting their ("potential") cross-
fertilization.
I see here a serious paradox
in that the paper seems necessarily to take its own theoretical basis as a sort
of unifying meta-orientation, and at the same time negating both the possiblity
and desirability of a unifying research paradigm or "unifying theoretical
straitjacket" or "common conceptual platform".
It is certainly possible to
try to escape the paradox by juggling around with ad-hoc differential
definitions of paradigm, orientation, conceptual structure, conceptual
framework, conceptual roof, theoretical basis, etc.. I think, however, that the
reader is justified in having a certain skepsis regarding the import of the
conclusions. The paper aims at stimulating pluralism and debate in the spirit
of what nowadays if often called networking. It can, however, be understood or
misunderstood as backfiring either in good old eclecticism that is seldom if
ever considered in such contexts, or in the by now sadly known direction of
postmodern relativism.(2)
In its conclusions the paper
also misses the possibility that an increasing number of incompatible paradigms
that try to account for disparate observations can be caused by inherent
inadequacies of the theoretical base. The less one understands, the more, and
more pluralistically, one needs or wants to "know". This recalls
statements such as that if computers had been available at the time of the
Copernican revolution, such revolution might never have taken place.(3) Pluralism
might indeed have taken care of the problems even in the instrumental and
strategic domains.
As far as I can see, these
are issues that are not addressed in the paper, unless the reader is supposed
to consider them implicitly solved in its theoretical base with its all
encompassing ambitions.
Theoretical basis
In my view the main merit of
the authors is that, by now for more than ten years, they have contributed in
the Anglo-Saxon scientific community to the attempts to transcend the narrow
technical view of our field. Some of us have looked into certain kinds of
systems theory like Churchman's The Design of Inquiring Systems (1971; 1979)
which discusses basic assumptions of ISD in philosophical terms including
theological concerns. The paper, however, draws inspiration from one particular
so called theory of social action by Jurgen Habermas: Theory of Communicative
Action (1984; 1987). In doing so it does not abstain from a rich use of the
undefined concept of system as it is more or less explicit in the use of
frequently used words like information system, object system, integration,
relation and interrelations, coherent framework, etc. There is probably no
space to state the basic assumptions and the metaphysics of Habermas' ideas for
understanding modern societies. Habermas' treatment of smaller collectives or
organizations, as well as of technology, is, however, far less articulated. For
this reason the analytical framework is supplemented by elements from A.
Etzioni's The Active Society (1968).
While a philosopher like
Churchman, for instance, forcefully explains the difficulties of pluralism
vis-a-vis monism (1971, p. 71ff), Habermas apparently opens the way for what I
would call orientational relativism. In the paper,Habermas' four "orientations"
(instrumental, strategic, communicative, and discursive) are assumed to
"capture the mind sets that guide the purposeful actions" of
participants (and other concerned?) in ISD. They are also supposed to enable
discussion of the assumptions that can be made about the general human
intentions which drive ISD, and of the behavioral strategies that can be
pursued during ISD to realize these intentions.
Disregarding what "mind
sets" are supposed to be in their supposedly mix of attitudes, beliefs,
assumptions, intentions, goals, values, drives, and whatnot, the authors,
however, acknowledge that Habermas is too general in stating what is being
changed. Etzioni's work, disregarding the issue of its compatibility with
Habermas, is therefore used in the paper in order to classify the outcomes of
ISD in three realms of action or domains of change (technology, organization,
and language).
What follows in the paper is
basically the treatment of all ISD research in terms of nine "object
classes" corresponding to all meaningful combinations of orientations and
types of changes. This recalls a remarkable and confusing difference from a
prior work of the authors that had an identical theoretical base. What is now
called objects classes was called there effectiveness measures, what is now
called domains of change was called object systems classes, and what is now
called orientations was called actions type classes.(4)
The final purpose seems
anyway to be to show that most if not all known research that can be associated
with IS and ISD can be related to these classes. Furthermore, the conclusions
indicate that the real ultimate purpose is twofold: to legitimate other
orientations than the so called instrumental and strategic ones, and to ask for
tolerance and for funds to support these alternative orientations.
For the moment I will
disregard the question of the definition of information systems (IS) in
general, and and their development (ISD) in particular. I also disregard
whether the tratment of ISD in terms of object classes "explains" its
development in terms of either causes of purposes. Despite the authors' obvious
admiration and devotion for Habermas, supported by authoritative quotations
from the work of other admirers, there are indeed "many application problems"
that remain unstated in the text.(5) They are briskly brushed aside in view of
the assumedly modest goals of the paper. The psychologycally and ethically
obscure category of orientation is nearly invalidated or postmodernly
relativized by the observation that actors can change their orientations very
quickly in ISD, and that actors can also adopt multiple orientations.
These kinds of problems may
indeed explain what seems to me the surprisingly innocence of the conclusions.
They disregard the reasons why humans have or adopt different orientations,
whatever they mean. They disregard whether such orientations are
psychologically correct or ethically justifiable at all (6). These questions
recall the mentioned but unspecified"application problems" of Habermas'
theory that supports the whole argument. These problems are ignored by the
authors also on the basis of a sweeping wholesale justification that "all
good theories in a state of change and development". This state of change or, rather,
process of change, has to do with they "call" for a constraint-free
situation or "ideal speech situation" which is supposed to be
attained by the paper's "instititutional democracy design" in view of
a "federated" ISD research framework.
Why "should" we
all strive for Habermas' sort of categorical imperative of an ideal speech
situation? Where does the belief in legitimacy and power of pluralism and of
democratic debate come from? Many believe that it comes from logic or from the
belief in logic. I think that it has deeper roots in the legacy of the
philosophy of Immanuel Kant by whom both Habermas and the authors of the paper
seem to be heavily influenced.
Federated pluralism and
debate
I am painfully aware that a
problematization of pluralism and debate is nowadays easily considered to be a
curse against the god of democracy. Such questioning in the scientific
establishment tends also to be seen as a curse in the invisible church of the
free market of ideas. It is fascinating to wonder how this is possible despite of
the paradoxical conclusions of the paper. The authors indeed observe that
debate is sometimes not welcome in the struggle for dominance of certain
paradigms or orientations. In a mood of "realpolitik" or political
realism I wish, however, to dwell upon the reason for this state of affairs.
The paper calls calls for a
coherent "federated" research framework. The value of the federation
lies in its supposed ability to tolerate or even encourage independence, and,
further, systematic democratic
debate. The reader should note the use of the concepts of federation and
independence. I myself would gladly identify such a federative problem as a
typical political systems problem. Federation, for me as for many others, is
system. The paper, however, does expressely prefer social action theories to
system theories. The problem then arises concerning the theoretical status of
political federationism, self- determination. My guess is that the background
ideas of the paper in this respect are "Kantian" inasmuch the authors,
especially in earlier works, refer often to the emancipatory, neohumanist
ideals of autonomy and such, in the light of Kantian enlightenment ethics.
Kantian thought, even more
than the Habermasian one, is prohibitively complex for common people who are
not professional philosophers. Scholars' wholesale reference to such thought
can therefore have unfortunate effects that are analog to the power over users
as exercised by systems professionals, as referenced (Markus, & Bjrn-
Andersen, 1987) in the bibliography of the very same paper that we are
commenting. I direct therefore the reader to a work by Elie Kedourie, a
political scientist and historian who discusses some basic tenets of Kantian
ethics in their historical context.(7) I subscribe, in what follows, to his
views on the issue, consistent as they are with my own earlier modest attempts
to problematize some of the applications of Kantian ethics to our field.(8)
The Kantian view holds that
man is free when he obeys the laws of morality which he finds within himself,
not in the external world or in obedience to some external authority. Man must
obey these laws of morality by his free will. The good will, which is the free
will, is also the autonomous will. The logic of this doctrine was carried further.
The end of man was to determine himself, as a free being, self-ruling and
self-moved, (as if in the more or less implicit ethics of
"autopoietic" approaches to ISD). Religion, rightly understood, was
the perpetual quest for perfection. Intimate conviction, needing support from
nothing external, came to be seen as the true guide to political action. Once
convinced that a course of action is right, the righteous man has
unconditionally and uncompromisingly to realize the dictates of reason as
revealed to him.(9) Autonomy is made the essential end of politics. A good man
is an autonomous man. Self-determination thus becomes the supreme political
good. For its sake Kant is prepared to accept brutality; to it he subordinates
all other benefits of social life; self-government is better than good
government. Struggle (cf. debates or so called constructive conversations) is
the guarantee of higher intentions and achievements.
This doctrine of Kant led to
philosophical and practical difficulties which in the political climate of the
time required emendations like those of Fichte, and the aggrandizement of the
roles of the state or "society". Kant, however, had allowed a central
place for struggle in the philosophy of history. This was elaborated further by
Fichte, Herder, Schleiermacher, and others. Even political peace and progress
would then be maintained by the equilibrium of powers in liveliest competition
and in continuous change (cf. the paper's call for pluralism, diversification,
and interrelation). Diversity, as much as struggle is, then, a fundamental
characteristic of the universe, and diversity must be maintained within the
federated frame of autonomy and self-determination. Action becomes
understanding and understanding becomes action (as in today's much celebrated
but seldom evaluated so called action research, and in social action theory).
Intellectuals began to yearn for the life of action and of politics in a way
that to me resembles today' ambitions of a science of design amidst the
integration of research with industry and business. "By means of high
philosophical words rulers can better control the ruled, who are ensnared by
their literacy, and obtain their support or their passive acquiescence. Thus,
by a natural development, it is not philosophers who become kings, but kings
who tame philosophers to their use."(10)
It would have been
interesting if the authors of the paper had reflected upon their own their own
position, as philosophers or systems developers or whatever, differentiated
from plain "researchers" in the context of power and science. They
may indeed be putting themselves at the unstated level of metadesigners or
matrix designers, or in the lower right cell of the matrixes, corresponding to
the most sophisticated options like organizational sense-making and
institutional democracy design. I see in any case the affirmation of the
legitimacy of non unified paradigmatic commitments and orientations in ISD as
an analog to Kedourie's nationalistic diversity. The same analogy with nationalism
seems meaningful for the paper's repeated exhortation that paradigmatically
limited researchers should not rely on a strong consensus with their own
colleagues, but, rather, rely on some outside community or sub-community for
support.(11) This is,.of course, still more tempting in our networked age of Internet/World Wide Web and of
universities whose institutional structures crumble under the weight of
commercialization of research.
This sort of thoughts as
above, melting both liberal and socialistic overtones that are identifiable in
later marxist development, indicate, in my understanding, some modern roots of
the belief in pluralism.Without such roots it seems to be impossible to
understand the call that the authors of the paper, and other admirers of
Habermas, make for the counterfactual and patently absurd formal- procedural,
ethical-political conditions of argumentation in the so called ideal speech
situation: absence of constraints and of dominance of power, etc. And then we
have also the paper's Habermasian call for honest search for truth through
argumentation, and for "universal validity claims" of
intelligibility-comprehensibility, veracity- sincerity, accuracy, and social
appropriateness. They must be the Habermasian version of Kant's categorical
imperative, in the context of Habermas' substitution of language for Kant's
psychology or the original Frankfurt's school's psychoanalysis. Without such a
Kantian- ethical understanding of the Habermasian appeals or claims, it seems
unavoidable to perceive them as empty or politically-ethically naive wishful
thinking, in line with the surprising conclusions of the paper. In fact such
conclusions do not even portray a reflective consciousness of applicability (to
the scientific community) of the paper's own prior suggestions for political
organization design (POD), much less for institutional democracy design (IDD).
Motivation and purposes
The purposes of the paper,
according to alternative and repeated formulations, are to achieve:
1) a clear theoretical
foundations for the field of information systems (IS) or a conceptual
foundation for future theories of information systems development (ISD),
2) a conceptual structure or
coherent framework to understand, structure, relate and interpret the core
research results from different intellectual structures or schools of thought
in ISD, giving a theoretical explanation of why the field is a "fragmented
adhocracy" pointing out core areas of ISD research, suggesting
underdeveloped research areas for future research efforts, and questioning the
wisdom to cultivate a unifying research paradigm for the IS field,
3) a framework that provides
categories for making sense of the diversity and plurality of the field,
helping to interpret and relate the research literature and to understand the
co-evolution and de- evolution of diverse research concerns: interrelating the
results of the diverse adhocratic research communities under a general
conceptual roof,
4) demonstrating that a
"federated" ISD research framework is possible and desirable, because
it helps to understand the dynamics and establishment of the fragmented
adhocracy, abilitating to tolerate or even encourage independence, and yet
providing some structure and vocabulary to cross different intellectual
communities: to supply a prespecified tool-kit and accurate road maps such that
those committed to a paradigm can set out on an expedition in order to explore
the terrain.
This is contrasted with what
the authors judge is neither possible nor desirable to achieve, that is
A) a common conceptual
platform, paradigm, or a unifying theoretical straitjacket on which to ground,
build and organize IS research, or
B) widely accepted,
legitimized results or procedures on which one must build in order to construct
knowledge claims which are regarded as competent and useful contributions, or
C) a core set of consistent
assumptions that are held by a specific research community and which guide its
research agenda on generally recognized common puzzles.
The statements of goals of
the paper are apparently softened by the disclaimer that the analysis should
neither be seen as necessarily the "right way" to interpret the
field, nor in a normative context. The goals of the paper are claimed to be
"purely generative and analytic": generative in the sense of building
a framework for classification, and analytic in the sense of analyzing the
field based on the classification that provides further insights of the
intellectual structuring of the IS field.
This kind of vague
disclaimers, together the erlier mentioned disclaimers about the stability of
concepts like orientation, undermine the value of most conclusions. With
reservations for my own shortcomings I must profess that I do not think that
theoretical (meta-theoretical?) foundations, clear or not clear, have been
supplied for future theories of ISD, whatever theoretical foundations or theory
are or should be. In particular, I question the repeated use of words like
rational and analysis, while disregarding, under the mantle of Habermas, most
problems that have historically been considered in the context of rationalism
or irrationalism (Gardiner, 1967). This is the more remarkable in view of the
paper's repeated use of related rational words like clear, clarify and unambiguous,
consistent and coherent, logical analysis and analytic, rational, and such.
I do not think that the
paper has made sense of the diversity and plurality of the field, whatever
"making sense" means or should mean for those who do not know how it
is to be implicit in Habermas. Concerning the help to interpret and interrelate
research results I have got perhaps some help but I still cannot interpret or
interrelate them, whatever interpretation and interrelation means or should
mean. In particular I do not deem that seeing all these words in adjacent cells
of a matrix implies an interrelation in the meaning of, say, teleological
systems theory. It is still viable that some researchers will ask for more
funds for technology, since when technology works it will also be easier to
concentrate in studying social aspects and such. It can still be claimed that a
proper balance among different orientations requires one hundred times more
research resources for instrumental and strategic research. This can be so even
if one diregards the further pressures inherent in interests of the
industrial-commercial complex that promises jobs and welfare as a function of
technologically enhanced productivity. Some readers may even wish for more good
old marxist analyses here, as it was often the case in good old critical social
theory before Habermas.
And I do not deem that a
demonstration has been given that a federated ISD research is possible, with
ability to tolerate or encourage independence. Or, rather, it does seem to be
more necessary and valuable to know how this thing is to be achieved, assuming
that it is desirable, rather that to know that it is possible, as all utopias
seem to be possible.
Finally, I do not yet
understand, disregarding what understanding means or should mean, the dynamics
and establishment of fragmented adhocracy. I understand fragmented adhocracy to
be an expression of our lack or understanding of what this computer revolution
is all about and of where we are going, and why. The paper does not help me in
that quest since, for instance, it does not really address the interdependence
between the various orientations, granted that they are properly named and
defined within the greater whole about which nothing is said. And I do not
think that the a-historical word adhocracy is fortunate, since it hinders the
reader's from the possibilities to reflect about what has been learnt up to now
about, for example, pluralism, eclecticism, relativism, and nihilism.
The paper has its merits as
a further attempt to related ISD to philosophy and to some current of the
intellectual debate in the context of a increasingly receptive or tolerant
environment. This includes the opportunities to publish in the supporting
community. The authors have certainly contributed to this tolerance, but, as it
often is the case with tolerance, it can also stand for the sort of
indifference which is bestowed upon those who are not experienced as really
challenging or menacing the establishment. As a matter of fact, both Habermas and
Wittgenstein have become during the last 20 years a sort of profitable
"industry" of the West. They are barely controversial, possibly
because they are not dangerous for the establishment or they do not call into
question the dominant order of commonly accepted political, ethical, and
secular basic assumptions. In particular they do not question the importance of
instrumental technology and of business, but are, rather, understood as wishing
to complete them pluralistically with other orientations, leaving
interdependencies, and relative weights or priorities, undiscussed or up to the
political process. Therefore they can be met with silence by those dominant
trends that welcome the relativism and pluralism that allow them to continue
their dominance.
In this respect the paper
does not add much to the earlier 1991 publication by the same authors
(Lyytinen, et al., 1991), in the same way as my commentary here probably does
not add much to my earlier criticism of Habermasian and soft-systems influences
in our field (Ivanov, 1991b). The paper can, however, also be seen as a sort of
commented encyclopedic bibliography of a great number of papers and books from
which proper selections can be made for readings in undergraduate and graduate
academic studies. I guess that mainly the authors, and perhaps some readers,
experience the effort to write or read this encyclopedia as a catharsis or as
divestment of much frustration in not having being able to make sense of it
all. One is left at least with a sort of encyclopedic whole.
Even when considered as a
bibliography the collection could be. improved. Pioneer studies of social
issues of computing,with important
dimensions that remain underdeveloped as of today, are missing (Mowshowitz,
1976, 1977, 1981). The technological dimension, weak as it is in Habermas, is
also underdeveloped in this essay. Many technical references are to textbooks
with scanty historical value, or are more than ten years old. This can be
serious in view of rapid technical development and high rate of obsolescence
like, for instance, in computer networks. Other weaknesses are the scanty
attention given to the hot debates in human computer interaction (HCI) or
computer supported cooperative work (CSCW) where, for instance, cognitive
psychology meets psychosocial activity theory. Deeper questions of different
conceptions and "levels"of programming and software, as related to
the role and limitations of social applications of mathematics and logics, are
not addressed.(12) Issues of productivity are not considered: their deepening
would bring us to the most meaningful matters of sense making and argumentation
as found in the discussion of the rationalization of work.(13) The particular
definition that is adopted for IS and ISD ignores many contexts that are not
social unless the definition of social organization is widened to the point of
meaninglessness.(14) A lonely use of a personal computer hooked to the
Internet, like the use of an interactive TV-set or of a computerized artifact,
can disrupt the social organization of the family or raise new problems of
privacy despite of not relating clearly to social organization.(15)
Furthermore: no emphasis is given to the growth and metamorphosis of earlier
currents of participatory ISD into what today goes under the name of artefact
design, with more or less deep discussions of aristotelian concepts of
knowledge and reason, relations among logic, dialectics, and rhetorics; the
nature of mathematical-logical thought as embodied in the industrial computer
and as related to other types of knowledge; or relations between technology,
ethics and aesthetics of design.(16)
In view of the character and
magnitude of the challenge I deem that, for all its merits, it would be
unfortunate if the paper happens to encourage the reader to plunge into, and
get lost in, the Habermasian framework. To the extent that Habermasian politics
and ethics relies on Kantian thought, and with regard to the exercise of
"power over user-readers" by professional ISD systems-philosophers, I
wish to terminate by directing the reader to some excerpts from philosophical
literature that problematizes Kantian ethics.
Systems or learning in ISD
In "An essay on
philosophical method", the British historian and philosopher Robin
Collingwood refers to the confusions into which Kant is betrayed by his failure
to think out the relation between critical philosophy and metaphysics.(17)
Kant's plea for liberty of discussion in metaphysics rings true; but his reason
for defending it destroys the incentive for it; "for he argues that it can
do no harm, since it can come to no conclusion. Why then should we pursue it?
Because, says Kant, it is a useful gymnastic, in which reason comes to know
itself better". Collingwood goes on discussing two opposing views of the
relation between criticism and metaphysics: "Neither of these two opposing
views, taken by itself, truly represents Kant's thought. But they cannot be
reconciled except at the cost of revising anything he has told us about the
relation between his two kinds of philosophy. And further, in a chapter on
"the idea of system", Collingwood addresses his time's already
"postmodern" question of constructive thinking implying system, and
the common objections against finality, completeness, objectivity, and unity
(versus diversity) of systems. He concludes that the idea of system is
inevitable in philosophy. This idea is nowhere finally and completely realized;
"but it is always tending to realize itself wherever any diversity is
recognized in the subject-matter and methods of thought".(18)
It is possible to attempt to
counter this kind of criticism of what amounts to Habermasian pluralism by
establishing ad-hoc distinctions between philosophy and ISD orientations, and
such. I will not tire the reader by trying to pursue such hair splitting
arguments. I will, rather, refer to another recent approach, also by a
Kant-admirer, that echoes the same type of concerns for the consequences of
pluralist consequences of the application of misapplication of Kantian ethics.
In a recent paper, R.
Fuenmayor, one of the pioneers of so-called interpretive systemology
criticizes, as I see it, the relativism implied in substituting
"learning" for the earlier systems thinking.(Fuenmayor, 1995) The
author recalls that systems thinking was the hallmark of the type of modern
thinking represented by the Enlightenment and German idealism. This is patent
in the holistic character of Kant's critical thinking (reason). Reason, writes
Kant, is impelled by a tendency of "its nature" to the completion of
its course in a self-subsistent systematic whole. And this tendency is nothing
more than the "will to systems" of reason. Fuenmayor goes on noting
that before modernity, and even during the first part of modernity when Kantian
metaphysics was still alive, making holistic sense and moral acting were
non-separable. (cf. the Habermasian distinction between sense-making and
argumentation as related to social action.) The idea of "knowledge applied
to action" which lies at the essence of "methodology" and its
ethics, as we understand it the ISD-context of the present paper, would have
been meaningless.
In the philosopher
Heidegger's interpretation, the moral practical question "What ought I to
do?" (decision making on moral grounds) was a question addressed to the
totality, to the "ground of beings" or the Theos of presocratic
Greeks which we today understand as God. In Heidegger's arcane language,
however, there is a major problem in posing the practical question to theos,
which is not a manifested being but, rather concealment and mystery It is shown
as presence. When the theos shows itself there is something suprasensory
(presence, the way theos shows itself) apart from the sensory (apart from that-
which-becomes-present). The sensory depends upon the suprasensory. Types of
presence define metaphysical epochs.
Now, metaphysical thinking
"thinks beings as a whole with respect to Being (Theos). Hence
metaphysical thinking is systems thinking, thinking in terms of the ground or
Theos so that sense, holistic sense, be brought forth. The practical question
and making holistic sense are the same. The practical question is posed to a
representative of the epochal type of presence, be it "nature" or the
Church as the house of God on earth. What Kant attempted was to change the
representative (the Church) of the medieval type of presence (the Christian
God), so that human action can be autonomous. The whole work of the main
philosophers of modernity contributed to this revolutionary process, so that
the practical question could be posed directly to Theos, without intermediate
representative.
Reason, would be this new
type of presence, to be directly consulted without intermediary. Until Kant,
and still with Kant, Reason, however, is not a property of the human mind. It
is a type of presence before which humans have limited access. The first wave
of Modernity represents a new epoch in the history of metaphysics by which a
new type of presence is constituted, but the basic feature of metaphysical
thinking, systems thinking, remains. It still thinks beings as a whole, with
respect to Being or Theos. Fuenmayor concludes that this is how systems
thinking, contrary to what is common belief in our present (postmodern?)
systems community, was the hallmark of modern thinking.
One could think that the
shift from systems to learning, as in so called soft systems thinking and in
Habermasian communication, would be a call for emancipation and autonomy.
Fuenmayor remarks. however, that for instance the tradition of soft systems
thinking talks the language of "issues"and "accomodations among
conflicting interests", rather than "solutions". The notion of
accomodation within a given ontological order is not altered in its essence if
the circle of the affected is widened to all humans or if coercive contexts are
considered using a pluralistic "system of systems methodologies".(19)
In attempting to grasp the
type of order that accomodation (and, I would like to add, conversational
sense-making and argumentative negotiation) is striving for to maintain,
Fuenmayor recalls Nietzches's famous dictum that God is dead. That means,
according to Heidegger, much more than people do not believe simply in God any
more. It means the overturning of metaphysics implying the oblivion of the metaphysical
totality, and the arrival of the postmodern epoch characterized by what he
calls "enframing". Despite of all talk on freedom, democracy, and
rationality everything is accomodated to the status of
"standing.reserve" for being used in the technological way of
revealing. The type of presence disappears, and Theos has no way to show
itself. The two realms of being that characterize metaphysics are reduced to
one that does not appear as depending on anything. The suprasensory is
transformed into an unstable product of the sensory. And with such a debasement
of its antithesis, the sensory denies its own essence, and it culminates in
meaninglessness.
The reader might observe how
much of Heidegger's thought as referred by Fuenmayor is absent in the wholesale
referral to his philosophy in some of
late ISD-literature. Repeated mention is made there of throwness,
background (ready-to-hand), breakdown (present-at hand), etc., but Heidegger's
discussions of systemic metaphysics, not to mention his conception of
mathematics that is embodied in computer artifacts, find no place in the
discussions of acquisition of skill and design in ISD.(20) I sense this
phenomenon as a sympton of the death of metaphysics, and therefore of morality,
among those who today read Heidegger in an unconscious enframing mode of
design. This includes also de debasement of philosophical pragmatism to the
utilitarianism of its coarse oversimplifications.
I still have considered this
criticism by Fuenmayor because I think that it is applicable also to the
Habermasian framework, that needs to be "de-mystified". In any case I
myself consider the existential language launched by Heidegger as a desperate
secular attempt to talk about God and religion without daring to ackowledge
them and without even mentioning the words. In this sense I understand that
Heidegger attempts the same "heroic" deed of those who today, 2000
years after Aristotle, try to revive his philosophy without its Christian
counterparts like Thomas Aquinas etc. They try to reinstate some sense in the
midst of increasing senselessness of supposed aimless "learning".(21)
It is the senselessness of networked Internet- communication, conversation, and
hypermedia edutainement, the aesthetic-rhetorical educational entertainements
that are being substituted for both argumentation and tradition. And this
happens while industry and business are encouraged to run their smart and
hopefully profitable computerized mathematical models. It is the paradoxical
legitimation of senseless irrationality of consumption being matched by the
senseless superrationality of production.(22)
Conclusions of this
commentary
I hope that my main point in
this commentary, and my choice are clear. Metaphysics and theology must be
reinstated in ISD research. If ISD- philosophers are going to preach, it is
necessary that they know the historical meaning of preaching as a guide to what
to preach. That could be a fruitful complement to the expression of pious hopes
within the frame of a system of orientations that puts forward shoulds and oughts, categorical
imperatives and universal validity claims.(23)
Such a suggestion need not
be more utopian than the implications of the argumentation position presented.
I would like to terminate by paraphrasing the implementation strategy that the
paper suggests for the argumentation orientation, despite of the fact that the
authors had earlier associated strategy with the control orientation: I am
implying that the implementation must be concerned with instilling metaphysical
and Christian principles that work as check and balances in argumentation, in
democratic decision making and in policy formulation. A specific implementation
problem is to change social attitudes of organizational actors so that
metaphysical principles of love and justice are elevated above social norms of
conformity and acceptance of customs and traditions like conceptions of
rationality and analysis.
References
Barnouw, J. (1990). The
separation of reason and faith in Bacon and Hobbes, and Leibniz's Theodicy. In
J. W. Yolton (Ed.), Philosophy, religion and science in the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries (pp. 206-227).
Rochester, NY: Univ. of Rochester Press.
Buckley, M. J. (1987). At
the origins of modern atheism . New Haven and London: Yale University Press.
Bhler, E. (1970).
Conscience in economic life. In H. Zbinden et al (Ed.), Conscience (pp.
43-77). Evanston: Northwestern
University Press.
Brjeson, B. (1989). Is the
rationality of Habermas really rational? Seminar on sociology of science.
Controversies in science and society: Ethics and the implementation of science
in society. Dubrovnic, 8-19 May 1989.
Campbell, C. (1987). The
romantic ethic and the spirit of modern consumerism . New York:
Churchman, C. W. (1971). The
design of inquiring systems: Basic principles of systems and organization . New
York: Basic Books.
Churchman, C. W. (1979). The
systems approach and its enemies . New York: Basic Books.
Clarke, J. J. (1992). In
search of Jung: Historical and philosophical enquiries . London and New York:
Routledge.
Collingwood, R. G.
(1933/1970). An essay on philosophical method . Oxford: Clarendon Press.
de Raadt, D., J.R. (1991).
Information and managerial wisdom . Pocatello, Id.: Paradigm.
Etzioni, A. (1968). The
active society: Theory of societal and political processes . New York: The Free
Press.
Ferrara, A. (1985). A
critique of Habermas' Diskursethik. Telos, 64, 45-74.
Ferrara, A. (1987). A
critique of Habermas' consensus theory of truth. 13, 39-67.
Fuenmayor, R. (1995). The
will to systems: From making sense to enframing. In K. Ellis, A. Gregory, &
B. Mears-Young (Ed.), Critical issues in systems theory and practice . New York: Plenum Press.
Gardiner, P. (1967).
Irrationalism. In P. Edwards (Ed.), The encyclopedia of philosophy. Vol. 3 (pp.
213-219). New York & London:
Macmillan & Collier Macmillan.
Gulyga, A. (1977). Immanuel
Kant . Gteborg: Daidalos. (Russian orig., 1977. English translation: Immanuel
Kant: His life and thought. Boston: Birkhauser, 1987.)
Habermas, J. (1984). The
theory of communicative action. Volume
I. Reason and the rationalization of society . Boston: Beacon Press.
Habermas, J. (1987). The
theory of communicative action. Volume II. Lifeworld and systems: A critique of functionalist
reason . Boston: Beacon Press.
Hayek, F. A. (1967). Studies
in philosophy, politics and economics . London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Heidegger, M. (1978). Modern
science, metaphysics, and mathematics. In D. F. Krell (Ed.), Martin Heidegger:
Basic writings (pp. 247-282).
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. (Orig. M.Heidegger Die Frage nach dem Ding.
Tbingen: Max Niemeyer, 1962, pp.50-83. Included in the Italian trans.
in La questione della cosa. Napoli: Guida, 1989, pp. 96-133.)
Hirschman, A. O. (1977). The
passions and the interests: Political argument for capitalism before its
triumph . Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press.
Ivanov, K. (1972).
Quality-control of information: On the concept of accuracy of information in
data banks and in management information systems . The University of Stockholm
and The Royal Institute of Technology. (Doctoral diss. Diss. Abstracts Int.
1974, Vol 35A, 3, p. 1611-A. Nat.
Techn. Info. Service NTIS No. PB-219297.)
Ivanov, K. (1991a).
Computer-supported human science or humanistic computing science? Steps toward
the evaluation of a humanistic computing science (UMADP-WPIPCS-41.91:3). Ume
University, Inst. of Information Processing. (Rev. ed. of paper presented at
the Tenth International Human Science Research Association Conference, August
18-22, 1991, Gothenburg.)
Ivanov, K. (1991b). Critical
systems thinking and information technology. J. of Applied Systems Analysis,
18, 39-55. (Report UMADP-RRIPCS 11.90, Univ. of Ume, Inst. of Information
Processing. ISSN 0282-0579.)
Ivanov, K. (1993a). Belief
and reason, power and heroism in the task of the systems designer: Commented
selections on presuppositions of participatory cooperative argumentative design
and change (UMADP- WPIPCS-47.93.2, ISSN 0282-0587). Ume University, Inst. of
Information Processing. (2nd rev. ed.)
Ivanov, K. (1993b).
Hypersystems: A base for specification of computer-supported self-learning
social systems. In C. M. Reigeluth, B. H. Banathy, & J. R. Olson (Ed.),
Comprehensive systems design: A new educational technology (pp. 381-407). New York: Springer- Verlag. (Also as
research report, Ume University, UMADP-RRIPCS- 13.91, ISSN 0282-0579.)
Ivanov, K. (1995). The
search for a theory of hypermedia. In D. Dahlbom, F. Kammerer, F Ljungberg, J.
Stage, & C. Sorensen (Ed.), Proceedings of IRIS 18 (pp. 283-293). (Gothenburg Studies in Informatics,
Report 7.)
Jung, C. G. (1953-1979).
Collected Works - CW (20 volumes) . Princeton: Princeton University Press.
(R.F.C. Hull et al., Trans.)
Kedourie, E. (1960/1993).
Nationalism . London: Blackwell. (Swedish trans. Nationalismen: En studie av
nationalismen som ideologi. Stockholm, SNS, 1995.)
Lasch, C. (1977). Haven in a
heartless world: The family besieged . New York: Basic Books.
Lindbom, T. (1983). The
tares and the good grain: The kingdom of man at the hour of reckoning . Macon,
Ga: Mercer University Press. (Trans. by Alvin Moore Jr from Swedish: Agnarna
och Vetet, Stockholm: Norstedt, 1974. French trans. L'ivraie et le bon grain,
published in Milan: Arch, 1976. Spanish trans. La semilla y la cizaa, Madrid: Taurus Santillana, 1980.)
Lindbom, T. (1995).
Modernismen . Bors: Norma.
Lyytinen, K., Klein, H.,
& Hirschheim, R. (1991). The effectiveness of office information systems: A
social action perspective. J. of Information Systems, 1, 41-60.
Markus, M. L., &
Bjrn-Andersen, N. (1987). Power over users: Its exercise by systems
professionals. Communications of the ACM, 30(6, June), 498-504.
McCarthy, T. (1984). The
critical theory of Jrgen Habermas .. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Mowshowitz, A. (1976). The
conquest of will: Information processing in human affairs . Reading, Mass.:
Addison-Wesley.
Mowshowitz, A. (Ed.) (1977). Inside information: Computers
in fiction. Reading, Mass.:
Addison-Wesley.
Mowshowitz, A. (1981). On
approaches to the study of social issues in computing. Communications of the
ACM, 24(3), 146-155.
Pournelle, J. (1995).
Privacy and liberty. Byte, (June), 249-256.
Ramirez, J. L. (1995).
Skapande mening: En begreppsgenealogisk underskning om rationalitet, vetenskap
och planering. [Creative meaning: A contribution to a human-scientific theory
of action] . Stockholm: NORDPLAN - Nordiska Institutet fr Samhllsplanering.
Address: Biblioteket, Box 1658, S-11186 Stockholm, fax +46 8 4635401. (Doctoral
diss. No. 13:2. To be completed with No. 13:3, On meningens nedkomst: En studie i antropologisk tropologi.
English summary in Skapande mening: Presentation av ett avhanligsarbete i
humanvetenskaplig handlings- och planeringsteori 1984-1994, No. 13:1.
Bilbiography of about 300 entries on pp. 381-405.)
Riley, P. (1986). The
general will before Rousseau: The transformation of the divine into the civic .
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Sanne, C. (1995). Arbetets
tid [Working hours in the age of work: Working time reforms and consumption in
the welfare state] . Stockholm: Carlssons. (Doctoral diss. English summary and
bibliography of about 300 entries, pp. 275-341.)
Sass, L. A. (1992). Madness
and modernism . New York: Basic Books.
Stolterman, E. (1991).
Designarbetets dolda rationalitet: En studie av metodik och praktik inom
systemutveckling [The hidden rationale of design work: A study in the
methodology and practice of system development] . Ume: Ume University.
(Doctoral diss. UMADP-RRIPCS 14.91.)
The Economist. (1995a).
Freedom and community: The politics of restoration. The Economist, (December
24th-January 6th), 67-70. (Cf. also Letters, in a subsequent The Economist, p.
6.)
The Economist. (1995b). Who
speaks for cyberspace? The Electronic Frontier Foundation went to Washington to
"hack government. Instead, it imploded. A cautionary tale on the politics
of cyberspace. The Economist, (January 14th), 81-82.
Thompson, J. B., & Held,
D., (Eds.). (1982). Habermas: Critical debates . London: Macmillan.
Truesdell, C. (1984). The
computer: Ruin of science and threat to mankind. In C. Truesdell (Ed.), An
idiot's fugitive essays on science (pp. 594-631). Berlin: Springer Verlag.
Ulrich, W. (1983). Critical
heuristic of social planning: A new approach to practical philosophy . Bern:
Paul Haupt.
van den Berg, A. (1989).
Habermas and modernity: A critique of the theory of communicative action.
Current perspectives in social theory. Vol. 10 . (Author at Dept. of Sociology, McGill University, 855
Sherbrook St. West, Montreal, Quebec H3A 2T7, Canada.)
Wojtyla, K. (1980). I
fondamenti dell'ordine etico . Citt del Vaticano: Libreria Editrice Vaticana.
NOTES 1)For a reminder of
many issues of explanation and understanding in an ethical and philosophical
context of knowledge that is not addressed in the paper, despite its apparent
ambitions of universal coverage, see for instance Barnouw, (1990, esp. p. 223).
2)As a matter of fact there
is a postmodern tendency in certain recent publications in the ISD field,
claiming that outmoded and unspecified systems thinking, and possibly even
social action thinking, be substituted by a sort of "network
thinking" that is supposed to be emerging in the Internet and
World-Wide-Web trendy developments. Modern development or destruction of the
family as social organization is sometimes given as an example. The only
references I like to mention in this context are the cultural criticism of this
type of thinking by Sass (1992) and Lasch (1977).
3)(Mowshowitz, 1976, p. 117;
Truesdell, 1984).
4)(Lyytinen, Klein, &
Hirschheim, 1991). In an earlier paper of mine (Ivanov, 1991a, p. 30-31n) I had
already reason to question the fruitfulness of such, what I called, a
mind-blowing classification exercise.
5)The reader may find it
problematic, however, that Habermas is endorsed by quotations of superlative
partisan remarks by his own supporters. I grant that Habermas has been much
more influential in quantitative terms during our historically short time span.
I would not, however, dare to bestow upon my favorite philosopher a similar
apology. It would suggest belief in a sort of social Darwinism in the sense of
the best survival of the fittest researchers, or belief in the success of
predestination in a Weberian sense. It would also weaken the reader's trust in
the critical mood of the author. For a somewhat more sober appreciation, see
Thompson (1982, esp. contributions by Heller, Ottmann, Hesse, and Giddens). For
outright criticism see van den Berg (1989); McCarthy, 1984; Ferrara, 1985;
Ferrara, 1987; Brjeson, 1989).
6)The paper quotes
superlative evaluations of Habermas' contributions to, among other fields,
psychology. The reader may therefore wish to compare, for instance, the so
called orientations with the painstaking creation of C.G. Jung's psychological
types (Jung, 1953-1979, Vol. 6) within the frame of a complex philosophical
tradition (Clarke, 1992). The closest correspondents to psychological types in
ISD research have gone under the label of cognitive styles. They are not
surveyed in this paper.
7)Kedourie (1960/1993, esp.
chaps. 2-4.) writes, in my view, a brilliant, short critical overview of
sociopolitical implications of Kantian ethics. I assume that nobody will choose
the easy way of classifying him as a traditionalist, further equated with
conservative. He does not seem to dare, however, to take the step beyond
negative criticism which probably would lead him to the dilemmas of
secularization as hinted at by Lindbom (1983; 1995, where Habermasian ideas
belong to the chapter on cultural radicalism, and possibly pp. 54ff) or other
less outspoken researchers (Buckley, 1987; Riley, 1986). For the rest of Kant's
work, and in order to
"empower" the user-reader, I direct him to the most brilliant, albeit
uncritical, short overview of his ideas by his admirer Gulyga (1977). Gulyga
also suggest (in chaps. 6-7) the aesthetic and ethical importance of work,
which has led to its "divinization" in the socialistic Scandinavian
tradition of self- determination, co-determination, participation or democracy
at the workplace. This background also explains why the Scandinavian emphasis
on these values in the seventies could turn so rapidly into today's
aestheticist emphasis on playfulness and skill at the human-computer interface,
as evidenced in certain trends of "design" in general and HCI-design
in particular. For an application of Gulyga, close to these issues, see Ivanov,
(1995). Problematizations of Kant's philosophy are, for the rest, found in e.g.
Max Scheler (1874-1928) and, further, Wojtyla (1980), following the pioneer
meta-criticism by J.G. Hamann (1730-1788). For some details, see Ivanov (1991b,
pp. 45-51; 1991a, p. 74n).
8)(Ivanov, 1991a; Ivanov,
1991b; Ivanov, 1993a; Ivanov, 1995)
9)This seems to me to be
akin to the implicit ethics of the so called rationalities of late currents of
neo-romantic ISD or computer artefact design which, as the autopoietic ones,
are not considered in the extensive overview and bibliography of the paper. Cf.
for instance the appeal to believe and follow one own's convictions as an
practical and ethical standpoint in ISD, considered as neo-romantic design, in
Stolterman (1991, p. 124) or in the paper's Habermasian encouragement to follow
one's paradigm. What is seldom if ever stated in this kind of ethics of
personal conviction, in absence of grand syntheses like Fichte's, is what to do
when different actors have opposing convictions or rationalities and do not
want further debate, argumentation or negotiation. They will soon look for
political support in various sub-communities. And the more a community is
fragmented in sub-communities, the easier will be to find one sub- community
that will do, helping in the general pluralist struggle or, ultimately, war.
Neo-romantic subjective ethics, such as the one that long dominated the German
cultural sphere, turns, then, rapidly into objective politics and war.
10)(Kedourie, 1960/1993, p.
43.). This would be consistent with the lack of real debate in the pluralist
context. Debate is substituted by the clash of actions in the political field.
11)Without further
qualification such a statement can be understood or misunderstood as running
counter the common, albeit problematic, wisdom of much science with Popperian
falsification, the crucial experiment, or the dialectical deadly enemy. These
seem to be still considered, and rightly so, to be more dependable than the
consensus of a coalition politics which stands close to the positivistic view
of a consensual reality "out there". They are also more dependable
than peer-reviews by peers of own choice from the own community's
"national" network. The analogy to nationalism is not far fetched.
The Scandinavian ideology of the seventies concerning participation in ISD or
"democratization of work" was heavily inspired by Yugoslavian
experiences, the "praxis group" etc., that it is not opportune to
mention today. It seems that the Yugolavian industry's and the military's
workplaces were supposed to integrate denied or suffocated incompatibilities of
nationalistic pluralism, under a Kantian-Marxist umbrella of workers' autonomy.
12)Cf. P. Natorp's
"social idealism" belonging to the neo-kantian Marburg school. It is
cursorily touched upon through the paper's second-hand's reference to
E.Cassirer, without, however, relating to these issues. For a rough
introductory orientation, see the hints in Ivanov (1991a, pp. 36-38). The
relation or interdependence between formal and social science in also implicit
in the missing discussion of the definition of information, which indeed is a
prerequisite for the paper's definition of IS and ISD. (Ivanov, 1972, chap. 4;
Churchman, 1971, chaps. 7 and 9, both deal with such a definition that is
absent in the proposed Habermasian framework}.
13)See Hirschman (1977),
Campbell (1987) and other literature in English, as referenced by Sanne (1995).
14)Without subscribing to
his liberal philosophy, I wish to point out that this is akin to Hayek's
criticism in the essay "What is social? What does it mean?" (Hayek,
1967, pp. 237-247).
15)As an example, it is
difficult to see whether the proposed framework has anything to contribute to
the new issues of privacy and
liberty on the net, as presented by, say, Pournelle, (1995) or The Economist (1995b).
16)Cf. my own early
attention to fronesis (phronesis) in Ivanov (Ivanov, 1991a, pp. 46-48; Ivanov,
1993a; 1995). Scandinavian readers can also refer to a recent monumental work
in Swedish (albeit not specifically addressing ISD) by Ramirez, (1995, esp. pp.
78, 111f, 117, 143, 157-165, 216, 246, 288, 331). It includes learned
discussions of relations of Theoria-Episteme, Poiesis-Techne, Praxis- Fronesis,
etc., which also imply elusive relations between form, function, and structure
in design. What is missing with risk for unintended relativism, as in Habermas
work, is the connection to Christian thought that has historically complemented
the Greek heritage as basis of Western culture. See, finally, Ivanov (1995), in
view of the latest hot issues of fashionable hypermedia.
17)(Collingwood, 1933/1970,
pp. 23f, 177ff, 191ff)
18)Collingwood suggests
advancing from the conception of overlapping classes of philosophical topics to
the conception of a "scale of forms". "The various parts which
together make up the body of a philosophy will thus form a scale in whose
ascent the subject-matter becomes progressively philosophical...". But
"however far up the scale goes, he [the philosopher] never comes to an
absolute end of the series, because he already comes in sight of new problems;
but he is always at a relative end, in the sense that, wherever he stands, he
must know where he stands and sum up his progress henceforth..." The
reader is directed to the similarity between this philosophical treatment of
diversity which is lacking in the present paper's Habermasian account, and the
"sweeeping in" process described by Churchman or the "multimodal
thinking" described by de Raadt, or in my own "hypersystem"
(Churchman, 1971; de Raadt, 1991; Ivanov, 1993b) It is the inherent limitation
of this relatively advanced thinking that has led me to transcend it in favour
of non-market-oriented, non-competitive studies of "belief and
reason" (Ivanov, 1993a), and of "theological aesthetics"
(Ivanov, 1995).
19)Compare with
Habermas-Apel's system of orientations, ideal speech situation and universal
validity claims, as well as with Ulrichs critical heuristics (Ulrich, 1983). I
repeat that this was the reason for my going beyond my own conception of
hypersystems after sensing its limitations and the misuse of its pragmatist
background ideas by constructive-learning instrumentalists (Ivanov, 1993a;
Ivanov, 1993b).
20)(Heidegger, 1978, is but
one example of what does not find its way in the ISD.literature by many
Heidegger enthusiasts.)
21)(Ramirez, 1995). In a
personal communication (14 August 1995), prof. Lpez-Garay at the University of
the Andes, Mrida, Venezuela,
writes "I myself am trying to work out an answer to this question
from a MacIntyreian perspective. I
think the clue lies in MacIntyre's
notions of Tradition and the Unity of a Human Life. As you recall MacIntyre basis his arguments in
Aristotles and Thomas Aquinas'. Hence
the point is that Habermas does not take into account the trascendental
telos that gives unity to a human life and how this is related to a tradition.
The result is that ethical decisions are reduced to debate where the better
argument is the light that guides finally action, but where are taken into
consideration tradition, and the unity of a human life ---that is. the trascendental
telos that guides human action and which is nothing but the search for the
"good life"? Practical reason used solely in this Habermasian terms
becomes nothing but instrumental reason On the contrary, in Aristotles' and
Aquinas' terms we must search for the Good life and be trained and educated in
the virtues. Only with such an education we can firmly orient our search. The
purpose of moral life is to search the good life. The purpose of the search is
the Search!! For a non- academic
polemic on MacIntyre ("After Virtue", 1985) as related to Etzioni see
The Economist (1995a).
22)(Bhler, 1970; Sanne,
1995).
23)Scandinavian readers can
recognize the image of meaningless purpose of never-ending "trespassing of
all frontiers" in the last chapter of Tage Lindbom's recent work on
modernism (Lindbom, 1995, in Swedish). It includes the background of Habermas'
thought. The readers of English language can grasp some of the author's
thoughts in an earlier book that is the only one so far translated into English
(Lindbom, 1983).